The following is a conversation with Lee Smolin.
He’s a theoretical physicist,
co inventor of loop quantum gravity,
and a contributor of many interesting ideas
to cosmology, quantum field theory,
the foundations of quantum mechanics,
theoretical biology, and the philosophy of science.
He’s the author of several books,
including one that critiques the state of physics
and string theory called The Trouble with Physics.
And his latest book, Einstein’s Unfinished Revolution,
The Search for What Lies Beyond the Quantum.
He’s an outspoken personality in the public debates
on the nature of our universe,
among the top minds in the theoretical physics community.
This community has its respected academics,
its naked emperors, its outcasts and its revolutionaries,
its madmen and its dreamers.
This is why it’s an exciting world to explore
through a long form conversation.
I recommend you listen back to the episodes
with Leonard Susskind, Sean Carroll, Michio Okaku,
Max Tegmark, Eric Weinstein, and Jim Gates.
You might be asking, why talk to physicists
if you’re interested in AI?
To me, creating artificial intelligence systems
requires more than Python and deep learning.
It requires that we return to exploring
the fundamental nature of the universe and the human mind.
Theoretical physicists venture out into the dark,
mysterious, psychologically challenging place
of first principles more than almost any other discipline.
This is the Artificial Intelligence Podcast.
If you enjoy it, subscribe on YouTube,
give it five stars on Apple Podcast,
support it on Patreon, or simply connect with me on Twitter
at Lex Friedman, spelled F R I D M A N.
As usual, I’ll do one or two minutes of ads now
and never any ads in the middle
that can break the flow of the conversation.
I hope that works for you
and doesn’t hurt the listening experience.
This show is presented by Cash App,
the number one finance app in the App Store.
When you get it, use code LEXBODCAST.
Cash App lets you send money to friends,
buy Bitcoin, and invest in the stock market
with as little as one dollar.
Since Cash App allows you to buy Bitcoin,
let me mention that cryptocurrency
in the context of the history of money is fascinating.
I recommend Ascent of Money as a great book on this history.
Debits and credits on ledgers
started around 30,000 years ago.
The US dollar, of course, created over 200 years ago,
and Bitcoin, the first decentralized cryptocurrency,
was released just over 10 years ago.
So given that history, cryptocurrency is still very much
in its early days of development,
but it still is aiming to
and just might redefine the nature of money.
If you get Cash App from the App Store or Google Play
and use the code LEXBODCAST, you’ll get $10,
and Cash App will also donate $10 to First,
one of my favorite organizations
that is helping to advance robotics and STEM education
for young people around the world.
And now, here’s my conversation with Lee Smolin.
What is real?
Let’s start with an easy question.
Put another way, how do we know what is real
and what is merely a creation
of our human perception and imagination?
We don’t know.
This is science.
I presume we’re talking about science.
And we believe, or I believe,
that there is a world that is independent of my existence
and my experience about it and my knowledge of it,
and this I call the real world.
So you said science, but even bigger than science, what?
Sure, sure.
I need not have said this is science.
I just was warming up.
Warming up?
Okay, now that we’re warmed up,
let’s take a brief step outside of science.
Is it completely a crazy idea to you
that everything that exists is merely a creation
of our mind?
So there’s a few, not many.
This is outside of science now.
People who believe sort of perception
is fundamentally what’s in our human perception,
the visual cortex and so on,
the cognitive constructs that’s being formed there
is the reality.
And then anything outside is something
that we can never really grasp.
Is that a crazy idea to you?
There’s a version of that that is not crazy at all.
What we experience is constructed by our brains
and by our brains in an active mode.
So we don’t see the raw world.
We see a very processed world.
We feel something that’s very processed through our brains
and our brains are incredible.
But I still believe that behind that experience,
that mirror or veil or whatever you wanna call it,
there is a real world and I’m curious about it.
Can we truly, how do we get a sense of that real world?
Is it through the tools of physics,
from theory to the experiments?
Or can we actually grasp it in some intuitive way
that’s more connected to our ape ancestors?
Or is it still fundamentally the tools of math and physics
that really allow us to grasp it?
Well, let’s talk about what tools they are.
What you say are the tools of math and physics.
I mean, I think we’re in the same position
as our ancestors in the caves
or before the caves or whatever.
We find ourselves in this world and we’re curious.
We also, it’s important to be able to explain
what happens when there are fires, when there are not fires,
what animals and plants are good to eat and all that stuff.
But we’re also just curious.
We look up in the sky and we see the sun and the moon
and the stars and we see some of those move
and we’re very curious about that.
And I think we’re just naturally curious.
So we make, this is my version of how we work.
We make up stories and explanations.
And where there are two things
which I think are just true of being human,
we make judgments fast because we have to.
Where to survive, is that a tiger or is that not a tiger?
And we go.
Act.
We have to act fast on incomplete information.
So we judge quickly and we’re often wrong
or at least sometimes wrong, which is all I need for this.
We’re often wrong.
So we fool ourselves and we fool other people readily.
And so there’s lots of stories that get told
and some of them result in a concrete benefit
and some of them don’t.
So you said we’re often wrong,
but what does it mean to be right?
Right, that’s an excellent question.
To be right, well since I believe that there is a real world,
I believe that to be, you can challenge me on this
if you’re not a realist.
A realist is somebody who believes
in this real objective world
which is independent of our perception.
If I’m a realist, I think that to be right
is to come closer.
I think first of all, there’s a relative scale.
There’s not right and wrong.
There’s right or more right and less right.
And you’re more right if you come closer
to an exact true description of that real world.
Now can we know that for sure?
No.
And the scientific method is ultimately
what allows us to get a sense
of how close we’re getting to that real world?
No on two counts.
First of all, I don’t believe there’s a scientific method.
I was very influenced when I was in graduate school
by the writings of Paul Fireman
who was an important philosopher of science
who argued that there isn’t a scientific method.
There is or there is not?
There is not.
Can you elaborate, I’m sorry if you were going to,
but can you elaborate on what does it mean
for there not to be a scientific method,
this notion that I think a lot of people believe in
in this day and age?
Sure.
Paul Fireman, he was a student of Popper
who taught Karl Popper.
And Fireman argued both by logic
and by historical example that you name anything
that should be part of the practice of science.
Say you should always make sure that your theories agree
with all the data that’s already been taken.
And he’ll prove to you that there have to be times
when science contradicts, when some scientist contradicts
that advice for science to progress overall.
So it’s not a simple matter.
I think that, I think of science as a community.
Of people.
Of people and as a community of people
bound by certain ethical precepts,
precepts, whatever that is.
So in that community, a set of ideas they operate under,
meaning ethically of kind of the rules of the game
they operate under.
Don’t lie, report all your results,
whether they agree or don’t agree with your hypothesis.
Check the training of a scientist.
Mostly consists of methods of checking
because again, we make lots of mistakes.
We’re very error prone.
But there are tools both on the mathematics side
and the experimental side to check and double check
and triple check.
And a scientist goes through a training
and I think this is part of it.
You can’t just walk off the street and say,
yo, I’m a scientist.
You have to go through the training
and the training, the test that lets you be done
with the training is can you form a convincing case
for something that your colleagues
will not be able to shout down
because they’ll ask, did you check this?
And did you check that?
And did you check this?
And what about seeming contradiction with this?
And you’ve got to have answers to all those things
or you don’t get taken seriously.
And when you get to the point where you can produce
that kind of defense and argument,
then they give you a PhD.
And you’re kind of licensed.
You’re still gonna be questioned
and you still may propose or publish mistakes.
But the community is gonna have to waste less time
fixing your mistakes.
Yes, but if you can maybe linger on it a little longer,
what’s the gap between the thing that that community does
and the ideal of the scientific method?
The scientific method is you should be able
to repeat and experiment.
There’s a lot of elements to what construes
the scientific method, but the final result,
the hope of it is that you should be able to say
with some confidence that a particular thing
is close to the truth.
Right, but there’s not a simple relationship
between experiment and hypothesis or theory.
For example, Galileo did this experiment
of dropping a ball from the top of a tower
and it falls right at the base of the tower.
And an Aristotelian would say, wow,
of course it falls right to the base of the tower.
That shows that the earth isn’t moving
while the ball is falling.
And Galileo says, no way, there’s a principle of inertia
and it has an inertia in the direction
where the earth isn’t moving and the tower
and the ball and the earth all move together.
When the principle of inertia tells you it hits the bottom,
it does look, therefore my principle of inertia is right.
And Aristotelian says, no, our style of science is right.
The earth is stationary.
And so you gotta get an interconnected bunch of cases
and work hard to line up and explain.
It took centuries to make the transition
from Aristotelian physics to the new physics.
It wasn’t done until Newton in 1680 something, 1687.
So what do you think is the nature of the process
that seems to lead to progress?
If we at least look at the long arc of science,
of all the community of scientists,
they seem to do a better job of coming up with ideas
that engineers can then take on and build rockets with
or build computers with or build cool stuff with.
I don’t know, a better job than what?
Than this previous century.
So century by century, we’ll talk about string theory
and so on and kind of possible,
what you might think of as dead ends and so on.
Which is not the way I think of string theory.
We’ll straighten out, we’ll get all the strings straight.
But there is, nevertheless in science, very often,
at least temporary dead ends.
But if you look at the, through centuries,
the century before Newton and the century after Newton,
it seems like a lot of ideas came closer to the truth
that then could be usable by our civilization
to build the iPhone, right?
To build cool things that improve our quality of life.
That’s the progress I’m kind of referring to.
Let me, can I say that more precisely?
Yes, well, it’s a low bar.
Because I think it’s important to get the time places right.
There was a scientific revolution that partly succeeded
between about 1900 or late 1890s
and into the 1930s, 1940s and so.
And maybe some, if you stretched it, into the 1970s.
And the technology, this was the discovery of relativity
and that included a lot of developments of electromagnetism.
The confirmation, which wasn’t really well confirmed
into the 20th century, that matter was made of atoms.
And the whole picture of nuclei with electrons going around,
this is early 20th century.
And then quantum mechanics was from 1905,
took a long time to develop, to the late 1920s.
And then it was basically in final form.
And the basis of this partial revolution,
and we can come back to why it’s only a partial revolution,
is the basis of the technologies that you mentioned.
All of, I mean, electrical technology
was being developed slowly with this.
And in fact, there’s a close relation
between the development of electricity
and the electrification of cities in the United States
and Europe and so forth.
And the development of the science.
The fundamental physics since the early 1970s
doesn’t have a story like that so far.
There’s not a series of triumphs and progresses
and there’s not any practical application.
So just to linger briefly on the early 20th century
and the revolutions in science that happened there,
what was the method by which the scientific community
kept each other in check about when you get something right,
when you get something wrong?
Is experimental validation ultimately the final test?
It’s absolutely necessary.
And the key things were all validated.
The key predictions of quantum mechanics
and of the theory of electricity and magnetism.
So before we talk about Einstein, your new book,
before String Theory, Quantum Mechanics, so on,
let’s take a step back at a higher level question.
What is that you mentioned?
What is realism?
What is anti realism?
And maybe why do you find realism,
as you mentioned, so compelling?
Well, realism is the belief in an external world
independent of our existence, our perception,
our belief, our knowledge.
A realist as a physicist is somebody who believes
that there should be possible some completely objective
description of each and every process
at the fundamental level, which describes and explains
exactly what happens and why it happens.
That kind of implies that that system,
in a realist view, is deterministic,
meaning there’s no fuzzy magic going on
that you can never get to the bottom,
or you can get to the bottom of anything
and perfectly describe it.
Some people would say that I’m not that interested
in determinism, but I could live with the fundamental world,
which had some chance in it.
So do you, you said you could live with it,
but do you think God plays dice in our universe?
I think it’s probably much worse than that.
In which direction?
I think that theories can change,
and theories can change without warning.
I think the future is open.
You mean the fundamental laws of physics can change?
Yeah.
Oh, okay, we’ll get there.
I thought we would be able to find some solid ground,
but apparently the entirety of it, temporarily so, probably.
Okay, so realism is the idea that while the ground
is solid, you can describe it.
What’s the role of the human being,
our beautiful, complex human mind in realism?
Do we have a, are we just another set of molecules
connected together in a clever way,
or the observer, does the observer, our human mind,
consciousness, have a role in this realism view
of the physical universe?
There’s two ways, there’s two questions you could be asking.
One, does our conscious mind, do our perceptions
play a role in making things become,
in making things real or things becoming?
That’s question one.
Question two is, does this, we can call it
a naturalist view of the world that is based on realism,
allow a place to understand the existence of
and the nature of perceptions and consciousness in mind,
and that’s question two.
Question two, I do think a lot about,
and my answer, which is not an answer, is I hope so,
but it certainly doesn’t yet.
So what kind?
Question one, I don’t think so.
But of course, the answer to question one
depends on question two.
Right.
So I’m not up to question one yet.
So question two is the thing that you can kind of
struggle with at this time.
Yes.
That’s, what about the anti realists?
So what flavor, what are the different camps
of anti realists that you’ve talked about?
I think it would be nice if you can articulate
for the people for whom there is not
a very concrete real world, or there’s divisions,
or it’s messier than the realist view of the universe,
what are the different camps, what are the different views?
I’m not sure I’m a good scholar and can talk about
the different camps and analyze it,
but some, many of the inventors of quantum physics
were not realists, were anti realists.
Their scholars, they lived in a very perilous time
between the two world wars.
And there were a lot of trends in culture
which were going that way.
But in any case, they said things like,
the purpose of science is not to give an objective
realist description of nature as it would be
in our absence.
This might be saying Niels Bohr.
The purpose of science is as an extension
of our conversations with each other
to describe our interactions with nature.
And we’re free to invent and use terms like
particle, or wave, or causality, or time, or space.
If they’re useful to us, and they carry some
intuitive implication, but we shouldn’t believe
that they actually have to do with what nature
would be like in our absence,
which we have nothing to say about.
Do you find any aspect of that,
because you kind of said that we human beings
tell stories, do you find aspects of that
kind of anti realist view of Niels Bohr compelling?
That we fundamentally are storytellers,
and then we create tools of space, and time,
and causality, and whatever this fun quantum
mechanic stuff is to help us tell the story of our world.
Sure, I just would like to believe that there’s
an aspiration for the other thing.
The other thing being what?
The realist point of view.
Do you hope that the stories will eventually lead us
to discovering the real world as it is?
Yeah.
Is perfection possible, by the way?
Is it? No.
Well that’s, you mean will we ever get there
and know that we’re there?
Yeah, exactly.
That’s not my, that’s for people 5,000 years in the future.
We’re certainly nowhere near there yet.
Do you think reality that exists outside of our mind,
do you think there’s a limit to our cognitive abilities?
Is, again, descendants of apes,
who are just biological systems,
is there a limit to our mind’s capability
to actually understand reality?
Sort of, there comes a point,
even with the help of the tools of physics,
that we just cannot grasp some fundamental aspects
of that reality.
Again, I think that’s a question
for 5,000 years in the future.
We’re not even close to that limit.
I think there is a universality.
Here, I don’t agree with David Deutsch about everything,
but I admire the way he put things in his last book.
And he talked about the role of explanation.
And he talked about the universality of certain languages
or the universality of mathematics
or of computing and so forth.
And he believed that universality,
which is something real,
which somehow comes out of the fact
that a symbolic system or a mathematical system
can refer to itself and can,
I forget what that’s called,
can reference back to itself and build,
in which he argued for a universality of possibility
for our understanding, whatever is out there.
But I admire that argument,
but it seems to me we’re doing okay so far,
but we’ll have to see.
Whether there is a limit or not.
For now, we’ve got plenty to play with.
Yeah.
There are things which are right there in front of us
which we miss.
And I’ll quote my friend, Eric Weinstein,
in saying, look, Einstein carried his luggage.
Freud carried his luggage.
Marx carried his luggage.
Martha Graham carried her luggage, et cetera.
Edison carried his luggage.
All these geniuses carried their luggage.
And not once before relatively recently
did it occur to anybody to put a wheel on luggage
and pull it.
And it was right there waiting to be invented
for centuries.
So this is Eric Weinstein.
Yeah.
What do the wheels represent?
Are you basically saying that there’s stuff
right in front of our eyes?
That once we, it just clicks,
we put the wheels on the luggage,
a lot of things will fall into place.
Yes, I do, I do.
And every day I wake up and think,
why can’t I be that guy who was walking through the airport?
What do you think it takes to be that guy?
Because like you said,
a lot of really smart people carried their luggage.
What, just psychologically speaking,
so Eric Weinstein is a good example of a person
who thinks outside the box.
Yes.
Who resists almost conventional thinking.
You’re an example of a person who by habit,
by psychology, by upbringing, I don’t know,
but resists conventional thinking as well,
just by nature.
Thank you, that’s a compliment.
That’s a compliment?
Good.
So what do you think it takes to do that?
Is that something you were just born with?
I doubt it.
Well, from my studying some cases,
because I’m curious about that, obviously,
and just in a more concrete way,
when I started out in physics,
because I started a long way from physics,
so it took me a long, not a long time,
but a lot of work to get to study it and get into it,
so I did wonder about that.
And so I read the biographies,
and in fact, I started with the autobiography of Einstein
and Newton and Galileo and all those people.
And I think there’s a couple of things.
Some of it is luck, being in the right place
at the right time.
Some of it is stubbornness and arrogance,
which can easily go wrong.
Yes.
And I know all of these are doorways.
If you go through them slightly at the wrong speed
or in the wrong angle, they’re ways to fail.
But if you somehow have the right luck,
the right confidence or arrogance, caring,
I think Einstein cared to understand nature
with ferocity and a commitment that exceeded
other people of his time.
So he asked more stubborn questions.
He asked deeper questions.
I think, and there’s a level of ability
and whether ability is born in or can be developed
to the extent to which it can be developed,
like any of these things like musical talent.
So you mentioned ego.
What’s the role of ego in that process?
Confidence.
But in your own life, have you found yourself
walking that nice edge of too much or too little,
so being overconfident and therefore
leaning yourself astray or not sufficiently confident
to throw away the conventional thinking
of whatever the theory of the day, of theoretical physics?
I don’t know if I, I mean, I’ve contributed
where I’ve contributed, whether if I had had
more confidence in something, I would have gotten further.
I don’t know.
Certainly, I’m sitting here at this moment
with very much my own approach to nearly everything.
And I’m calm, I’m happy about that.
But on the other hand, I know people
whose self confidence vastly exceeds mine.
And sometimes I think it’s justified
and sometimes I think it’s not justified.
Your most recent book titled
Einstein’s Unfinished Revolution.
So I have to ask, what is Einstein’s unfinished revolution
and also how do we finish it?
Well, that’s something I’ve been trying to do my whole life,
but Einstein’s unfinished revolution
is the twin revolutions which invented relativity theory,
special and especially general relativity,
and quantum theory, which he was the first person
to realize in 1905 that there would have to be
a radically different theory which somehow realized
or resolved the paradox of the duality
of particle and wave for photons.
And he was, I mean, people I think don’t always
associate Einstein with quantum mechanics
because I think his connection with it,
founding as one of the founders,
I would say, of quantum mechanics,
he kind of put it in the closet.
Is it?
Well, he didn’t believe that the quantum mechanics
as it was developed in the mid to late 1920s
was completely correct.
At first, he didn’t believe it at all.
Then he was convinced that it’s consistent,
but incomplete, and that also is my view.
It needs, for various reasons, I can elucidate,
to have additional degrees of freedom, particles,
forces, something to reach the stage
where it gives a complete description of each phenomenon,
as I was saying, realism demands.
So what aspect of quantum mechanics
bothers you and Einstein the most?
Is it some aspect of the wave function collapse discussions,
the measurement problem?
Is it the?
The measurement problem.
I’m not gonna speak for Einstein.
But the measurement problem, basically, and the fact that.
What is the measurement problem, sorry?
The basic formulation of quantum mechanics
gives you two ways to evolve situations in time.
One of them is explicitly when no observer is observing
and no measurement is taking place.
And the other is when a measurement
or an observation is taking place.
And they basically contradict each other.
But there’s another reason why the revolution
was incomplete, which is we don’t understand
the relationship between these two parts.
General relativity, which became our best theory
of space and time and gravitation and cosmology,
and quantum theory.
So for the most part, general relativity
describes big things.
Quantum theory describes little things.
And that’s the revolution that we found
really powerful tools to describe
big things and little things.
And it’s unfinished because we have
two totally separate things and we need to figure out
how to connect them so we can describe everything.
Right, and we either do that if we believe quantum mechanics
as understood now is correct by bringing general relativity
or some extension of general relativity
that describes gravity and so forth
into the quantum domain that’s called quantize,
the theory of gravity.
Or if you believe with Einstein
that quantum mechanics needs to be completed,
and this is my view, then part of the job
of finding the right completion
or extension of quantum mechanics
would be one that incorporated space, time, and gravity.
So, where do we begin?
So first, let me ask, perhaps you can give me a chance,
if I could ask you some just really basic questions.
Well, they’re not at all.
The basic questions are the hardest,
but you mentioned space, time.
What is space, time?
Space, time, you talked about a construction.
So I believe the space, time is an intellectual construction
that we make of the events in the universe.
I believe the events are real,
and the relationships between the events,
which cause which are real.
But the idea that there’s a four dimensional
smooth geometry which has a metric and a connection
and satisfies the equations that Einstein wrote,
it’s a good description to some scale.
It’s a good approximation, it captures some
of what’s really going on in nature.
But I don’t believe it for a minute is fundamental.
So, okay, we’re gonna allow me to linger on that.
So the universe has events, events cause other events.
This is the idea of causality.
Okay, so that’s real.
That’s in my.
In your view is real.
Or hypothesis, or the theories that I have been working
to develop make that assumption.
So space, time, you said four dimensional space
is kind of the location of things,
and time is whatever the heck time is.
And you’re saying that space, time is,
both space and time are emergent and not fundamental?
No.
Sorry, before you correct me,
what does it mean to be fundamental or emergent?
Fundamental means it’s part of the description
as far down as you go.
We have this notion.
As real.
Yes.
As real as real it could be.
Yeah, so I think that time is fundamental,
and quote goes all the way down,
and space does not, and the combination of them
we use in general relativity that we call space time
also does not.
But what is time then?
I think that time, the activity of time
is a continual creation of events from existing events.
So if there’s no events, there’s no time.
Then there’s not only no time, there’s no nothing.
So I believe the universe has a history
which goes to the past.
I believe the future does not exist.
There’s a notion of the present
and a notion of the past,
and the past consists of,
is a story about events that took place to our past.
So you said the future doesn’t exist.
Yes.
Could you say that again?
Can you try to give me a chance to understand that
one more time?
So events cause other events.
What is this universe?
Cause we’ll talk about locality and nonlocality.
Good.
Cause it’s a crazy, I mean it’s not crazy,
it’s a beautiful set of ideas that you propose.
But, and if Kozali is fundamental,
I’d just like to understand it better.
What is the past?
What is the future?
What is the flow of time?
Even the error of time in our universe, in your view.
And maybe what’s an event, right?
Oh, an event is where something changes,
or where two,
it’s hard to say because it’s a primitive concept.
An event is a moment of time within space.
This is the view in general relativity,
where two particles intersect in their paths,
or something changes in the path of a particle.
Now, we are postulating that there is,
at the fundamental level, a notion,
which is an elementary notion,
so it doesn’t have a definition in terms of other things,
but it is something elementary happening.
And it doesn’t have a connection to energy,
or matter, or exchange of energy?
It does have a connection to energy and matter.
So it’s at that level.
Yeah, it involves,
and that’s why the version of a theory of events
that I’ve developed with Marina Cortez,
and it’s, by the way, I wanna mention my collaborators,
because they’ve been at least as important
in this work as I have.
It’s Marina Cortez in all the work since about 2013,
2012, 2013, about causality, causal sets.
And in the period before that, Roberta Mangibera Unger,
who is a philosopher and a professor of law.
And that’s in your efforts,
together with your collaborators,
to finish the unfinished revolution.
Yes.
And focus on causality as a fundamental.
Yes.
As fundamental to physics.
So.
And there’s certainly other people we’ve worked with,
but those two people’s thinking
had a huge influence on my own thinking.
So in the way you describe causality,
that’s what you mean of time being fundamental.
That causality is fundamental.
Yes.
And what does it mean for space to not be fundamental,
to be emergent?
That’s very good.
There’s a level of description in which there are events,
there are events create other events,
but there’s no space.
They don’t live in space.
They have an order in which they caused each other.
And that is part of the nature of time for us.
But there is an emergent approximate description.
And you asked me to define emergent.
I didn’t.
An emergent property is a property
that arises at some level of complexity,
larger than and more complex than the fundamental level,
which requires some property to describe it,
which is not directly
explicable or derivable is the word I want
from the properties of the fundamental things.
And space is one of those things
in a sufficiently complex universe,
space, three dimensional position of things emerged.
Yes, and we have this,
we saw how this happens in detail in some models,
both computationally and analytically.
Okay, so connected to space is the idea of locality.
Yes.
So we’ve talked about realism.
So I live in this world that like sports.
Locality is a thing that you can affect things close to you
and don’t have an effect on things that are far away.
It’s the thing that bothers me about gravity in general
or action at a distance.
Same thing that probably bothered Newton,
or at least he said a little bit about it.
Okay, so what do you think about locality?
Is it just a construct?
Is it us humans just like this idea
and are connected to it because we exist in it,
we need it for our survival, but it’s not fundamental?
I mean, it seems crazy for it not to be
a fundamental aspect of our reality.
It does.
Can you comfort me on a sort of as a therapist,
like how do I?
I’m not a good therapist, but I’ll do my best.
Okay.
There are several different definitions of locality
when you come to talk about locality in physics.
In quantum field theory,
which is a mixture of special relativity
and quantum mechanics,
there is a precise definition of locality.
Field operators corresponding to events in space time,
which are space like separated,
commute with each other as operators.
So in quantum mechanics,
you think about the nature of reality as fields
and things that are close in a field
have an impact on each other more than farther away.
That’s, yes.
That’s very comforting.
That makes sense.
So that’s a property of quantum field theory
and it’s well tested.
Unfortunately, there’s another definition of local,
which was expressed by Einstein
and expressed more precisely by John Bell,
which has been tested experimentally and found to fail.
And this set up is you take two particles.
So one thing that’s really weird about quantum mechanics
is a property called entanglement.
You can have two particles interact
and then share a property
without it being a property
of either one of the two particles.
And if you take such a system
and then you make a measurement on particle A,
which is over here on my right side,
and particle B, which is over here.
Somebody else makes a measurement of particle B.
You can ask that whatever is the real reality
of particle B, it not be affected by the choice
the observer at particle A makes about what to measure,
not the outcome,
just the choice of the different things they might measure.
And that’s a notion of locality
because it assumes that these things
are very far spaced like separated.
And it’s gonna take a while for any information
about the choice made by the people here at A
to affect the reality at B.
But you make that assumption,
that’s called Bell locality.
And you derive a certain inequality
that some correlations,
functions of correlations have to satisfy.
And then you can test that pretty directly
in experiments which create pairs of photons
or other particles.
And it’s wrong by many sigma.
In experiment, it doesn’t match.
So what does that mean?
That means that that definition of locality
I stated is false.
The one that Einstein was playing with.
Yeah, and the one that I stated,
that is it’s not true that whatever is real
about particle B is unaffected by the choice
that the observer makes as to what to measure
in particle A.
No matter how long they’ve been propagating
at almost the speed of light or the speed of light
away from each other, it’s no matter.
So like the distance between them.
Well, it’s been tested, of course,
if you want to have hope for quantum mechanics
being incomplete or wrong and corrected
by something that changes this.
It’s been tested over a number of kilometers.
I don’t remember whether it’s 25 kilometers
or a hundred and something kilometers, but.
So in trying to solve the unsolved revolution,
in trying to come up with the theory for everything,
is causality fundamental and breaking away from locality?
Absolutely.
A crucial step.
So in your book, essentially, those are the two things
we really need to think about as a community.
Especially the physics community has to think about this.
I guess my question is, how do we solve?
How do we finish the unfinished revolution?
Well, that’s, I can only tell you what I’m trying to do
and what I’ve abandoned as not working.
As one ant, smart ant in an ant colony.
Yep.
Or maybe dumb, that’s why, who knows?
But anyway, my view of the,
we’ve had some nice theories invented.
There’s a bunch of different ones.
Both relate to quantum mechanics,
relate to quantum gravity.
There’s a lot to admire
in many of these different approaches.
But to my understanding,
they, none of them completely solve the problems
that I care about.
And so we’re in a situation
which is either terrifying for a student
or full of opportunity for the right student,
in which we’ve got more than a dozen attempts.
And I never thought, I don’t think anybody anticipated
it would work out this way.
Which work partly and then at some point,
they have an issue that nobody can figure out
how to go around or how to solve.
And that’s the situation we’re in.
My reaction to that is twofold.
One of them is to try to bring people,
we evolved into this unfortunate sociological situation
in which there are communities
around some of these approaches.
And to borrow again, a metaphor from Eric,
they sit on top of hills in the landscape of theories
and throw rocks at each other.
And as Eric says, we need two things.
We need people to get off their hills
and come down into the valleys and party and talk
and become friendly and learn to say,
not no but, but yes and yes.
Your idea goes this far,
but maybe if we put it together with my idea,
we can go further.
Yes.
So in that spirit, I’ve talked several times
with Sean Carroll, who’s also written
an excellent book recently.
And he kind of, he plays around,
is a big fan of the many worlds interpretation
of quantum mechanics.
So I’m a troublemaker.
So let me ask, what’s your sense of Sean
and the idea of many worlds interpretation?
I’ve read many the commentary back and forth.
You guys are friendly, respect each other,
but have a lot of fun debating.
I love Sean and he, no, I really,
he’s articulate and he’s a great representative
or ambassador of science to the public
and for different fields of science to each other.
He also, like I do, takes philosophy seriously.
And unlike what I do in all cases,
he has really done the homework.
He’s read a lot, he knows the people,
he talks to them, he exposes his arguments to them.
And I, there’s this mysterious thing
that we so often end up on the opposite sides
of one of these issues.
It’s fun though.
It’s fun and I’d love to have a conversation about that,
but I would want to include him.
I see, about many worlds, well.
No, I can tell you what I think about many worlds.
I’d love to, but actually on that, let me pause.
Sean has a podcast.
You should definitely figure out how to talk to Sean.
I would, I actually told Sean,
I would love to hear you guys just going back and forth.
So I hope you can make that happen eventually,
you and Sean.
I won’t tell you what it is,
but there’s something that Sean said to me
in June of 2016 that changed my whole approach to a problem.
But I’ll have to tell him first.
Yes, and that, that’ll be great to tell him on his podcast.
So.
I can’t invite myself to his podcast.
But I told him, yeah, okay, we’ll make it happen.
So many worlds.
Anyway.
What’s your view?
Many worlds, we talk about nonlocality.
Many worlds is also a very uncomfortable idea
or beautiful depending on your perspective.
It’s very nice in terms of,
I mean, there’s a realist aspect to it.
I think you called it magical realism.
Yeah.
It’s just a beautiful line.
But at the same time,
it’s very difficult to far limited human minds
to comprehend.
So what are your thoughts about it?
Let me start with the easy and obvious
and then go to the scientific.
Okay.
It doesn’t appeal to me.
It doesn’t answer the questions that I want answered.
And it does so to such a strong case
that when Roberto Mangueber Anger and I
began looking for principles,
and I want to come back and talk about
the use of principles in science,
because that’s the other thing I was going to say,
and I don’t want to lose that.
When we started looking for principles,
we made our first principle,
there is just one world and it happens once.
But so it’s not helpful to my personal approach,
to my personal agenda,
but of course I’m part of a community.
And my sense of the many worlds interpretation,
I have thought a lot about it and struggled a lot with it,
is the following.
First of all, there’s Everett himself,
there’s what’s in Everett.
And there are several issues there
connected with the derivation of the Born Rule,
which is the rule that gives probabilities to events.
And the reasons why there is a problem with probability
is that I mentioned the two ways
that physical systems can evolve.
The many worlds interpretation cuts off,
one, the one having to do with measurement,
and just has the other one, the Schrodinger evolution,
which is this smooth evolution of the quantum state.
But the notion of probability is only in the second rule,
which we’ve thrown away.
So where does probability come from?
And you have to answer the question
because experimentalists use probabilities
to check the theory.
Now, at first sight, you get very confused
because there seems to be a real problem
because in the many worlds interpretation,
this talk about branches is not quite precise,
but I’ll use it.
There’s a branch in which everything that might happen
does happen with probability one in that branch.
You might think you could count the number of branches
in which things do and don’t happen
and get numbers that you can define
as something like frequentist probabilities.
And Everett did have an argument in that direction,
but the argument gets very subtle
when there are an infinite number of possibilities,
as is the case in most quantum systems.
And my understanding,
although I’m not as much of an expert as some other people,
is that Everett’s own proposal failed, did not work.
There are then, but it doesn’t stop there.
There is an important idea that Everett didn’t know about,
which is decoherence,
and it is a phenomenon that might be very much relevant.
And so a number of people post Everett
have tried to make versions of what you might call
many worlds quantum mechanics.
And this is a big area and it’s subtle,
and it’s not the kind of thing that I do well.
So I consulted, that’s why there’s two chapters on this
in the book I wrote.
Chapter 10, which is about Everett’s version,
chapter 11, there’s a very good group of philosophers
of physics in Oxford, Simon Saunders, David Wallace,
Harvey Brown, and a number of others.
And of course there’s David Deutsch, who is there.
And those people have developed and put a lot of work
into a very sophisticated set of ideas
designed to come back and answer that question.
They have the flavor of there are really no probabilities,
we admit that, but imagine if the Everett story was true
and you were living in that multiverse,
how would you make bets?
And so they use decision theory
from the theory of probability and gambling and so forth
to shape a story of how you would bet
if you were inside an Everett in the universe
and you knew that.
And there’s a debate among those experts
as to whether they or somebody else has really succeeded.
And when I checked in as I was finishing the book
with some of those people, like Simon,
who’s a good friend of mine, and David Wallace,
they told me that they weren’t sure
that any of them was yet correct.
So that’s what I put in my book.
Now, to add to that, Sean has his own approach
to that problem in what’s called self referencing
or self locating observers.
And it doesn’t, I tried to read it
and it didn’t make sense to me,
but I didn’t study it hard,
I didn’t communicate with Sean,
I didn’t do the things that I would do,
so I had nothing to say about it in the book.
I don’t know whether it’s right or not.
Let’s talk a little bit about science.
You mentioned the use of principles in science.
What does it mean to have a principle
and why is that important?
When I feel very frustrated about quantum gravity,
I like to go back and read history.
And of course, Einstein, his achievements
are a huge lesson and hopefully something
like a role model.
And it’s very clear that Einstein thought
that the first job when you wanna enter a new domain
of theoretical physics is to discover and invent principles
and then make models of how those principles
might be applied in some experimental situation,
which is where the mathematics comes in.
So for Einstein, there was no unified space and time.
Minkowski invented this idea of space time.
For Einstein, it was a model of his principles
or his postulates.
And I’ve taken the view that we don’t know
the principles of quantum gravity.
I can think about candidates and I have some papers
where I discuss different candidates
and I’m happy to discuss them.
But my belief now is that those partially successful
approaches are all models,
which might describe indeed some quantum gravity physics
in some domain, in some aspect,
but ultimately would be important
because they model the principles
and the first job is to tie down those principles.
So that’s the approach that I’m taking.
So speaking of principles, in your 2006 book,
The Trouble with Physics, you criticized a bit
string theory for taking us away from the rigors
of the scientific method or whatever you would call it.
But what’s the trouble with physics today
and how do we fix it?
Can I say how I read that book?
Sure.
Because I, and I’m not, this of course has to be my fault
because you can’t as an author claim
after all the work you put in that you are misread.
But I will say that many of the reviewers
who are not personally involved
and even many who were working on string theory
or some other approach to quantum gravity
told me, communicated with me and told me
they thought that I was fair
and balance was the word that was usually used.
So let me tell you what my purpose was in writing that book,
which clearly got diverted by,
because there was already a rather hot argument going on.
And this is.
On which topic?
On string theory specifically?
Or in general in physics?
No, more specifically than string theory.
So since we’re in Cambridge, can I say that?
We’re doing this in Cambridge.
Yeah, yeah, of course.
Cambridge, just to be clear, Massachusetts.
And on Harvard campus.
Right, so Andy Straminger is a good friend of mine
and has been for many, many years.
And Andy, so originally there was this beautiful idea
that there were five string theories
and maybe they would be unified into one.
And we would discover a way to break that symmetries
of one of those string theories
and discover the standard model
and predict all the properties
of standard model particles,
like their masses and charges and so forth,
coupling constants.
And then there was a bunch of solutions
to string theory found,
which led each of them to a different version
of particle physics with a different phenomenology.
These are called the Calabi Yao manifolds,
named after Yao, who is also here.
Not, certainly we’ve been friends
at some time in the past anyway.
And then there were, nobody was sure,
but hundreds of thousands of different versions
of string theory.
And then Andy found there was a way
to put a certain kind of mathematical curvature
called torsion into the solutions.
And he wrote a paper, String Theory with Torsion,
in which he discovered there was,
and not formally uncountable,
but he was unable to invent any way
to count the number of solutions
or classify the diverse solutions.
And he wrote that this is worrying
because doing phenomenology the old fashioned way
by solving the theory is not gonna work
because there’s gonna be loads of solutions
for every proposed phenomenology
for anything the experiments discovered.
And it hasn’t quite worked out that way.
But nonetheless, he took that worry to me.
We spoke at least once, maybe two or three times about that.
And I got seriously worried about that.
And this is just a little.
So it’s like an anecdote that inspired
your worry about string theory in general?
Well, I tried to solve the problem
and I tried to solve the problem.
I was reading at that time, a lot of biology,
a lot of evolutionary theory,
like Linmar Gullis and Steve Gould and so forth.
And I could take your time to go through the things,
but it occurred to me,
maybe physics was like evolutionary biology
and maybe the laws evolved.
And there was, the biologists talk about a landscape,
a fitness landscape of DNA sequences
or protein sequences or species or something like that.
And I took their concept and the word landscape
from theoretical biology and made a scenario
about how the universe as a whole could evolve
to discover the parameters of the standard model.
And I’m happy to discuss,
that’s called cosmological natural selection.
Cosmological natural selection.
Yeah.
Wow, so the parameters of the standard model,
so the laws of physics are changing.
This idea would say that the laws of physics
are changing in some way that echoes
that of natural selection,
or just it adjusts in some way towards some goal.
Yes.
And I published that,
I wrote the paper in 1888 or 89,
the paper was published in 92.
My first book in 1997,
The Life of the Cosmos was explicitly about that.
And I was very clear that what was important
is that because you would develop an ensemble of universes,
but they were related by descent to natural selection,
almost every universe would share the property
that it was, its fitness was maximized to some extent,
or at least close to maximum.
And I could deduce predictions
that could be tested from that.
And I worked all of that out
and I compared it to the anthropic principle
where you weren’t able to make tests
or make falsifications.
All of this was in the late 80s and early 90s.
That’s a really compelling notion,
but how does that help you arrive?
I’m coming to where the book came from.
Yes.
So what got me,
I worked on string theory.
I also worked on loop quantum gravity.
And I was one of the inventors of loop quantum gravity.
And because of my strong belief in some other principles,
which led to this notion of wanting a quantum theory
of gravity to be what we call relational
or background independent,
I tried very hard to make string theory
background independent.
And it ended up developing a bunch of tools
which then could apply directly to general relativity
and that became loop quantum gravity.
So the things were very closely related
and have always been very closely related in my mind.
The idea that there were two communities,
one devoted to strings and one devoted to loops is nuts
and has always been nuts.
Okay, so anyway, there’s this nuts community
of loops and strings that are all beautiful
and compelling and mathematically speaking.
And what’s the trouble with all that?
Why is that such a problem?
So I was interested in developing that notion
of how science works based on a community
and ethics that I told you about.
And I wrote a draft of a book about that,
which had several chapters on methodology of science.
And it was a rather academically oriented book.
And those chapters were the first part of the book,
the first third of it.
And you didn’t find their remnants
in what’s now the last part of the trouble with physics.
And then I described a number of test cases, case studies.
And one of them, which I knew was the search
for quantum gravity and string theory and so forth.
And I wasn’t able to get that book published.
So somebody made the suggestion of flipping it around
and starting with a story of string theory,
which was already controversial.
This was 2004, 2005.
But I was very careful to be detailed,
to criticize papers and not people.
You won’t find me criticizing individuals.
You’ll find me criticizing certain writing.
But in any case, here’s what I regret.
Let me make your program worthwhile.
Yes.
As far as I know, with the exception of not understanding
how large the applications to condensed matter,
say ADS CFT would get,
I think largely my diagnosis of string theory
as it was then has stood up since 2006.
What I regret is that the same critique,
I was using string theory as an example,
and the same critique applies to many other communities
in science and all of, including,
and this is where I regret my own community,
that is a community of people working on quantum gravity.
Not science string theory.
But, and I considered saying that explicitly.
But to say that explicitly,
since it’s a small, intimate community,
I would be telling stories and naming names
and making a kind of history
that I have no right to write.
So I stayed away from that, but was misunderstood.
But if I may ask, is there a hopeful message
for theoretical physics that we can take from that book,
sort of that looks at the community,
not just your own work on,
now with causality and nonlocality,
but just broadly in understanding
the fundamental nature of our reality,
what’s your hope for the 21st century in physics?
Well, that we solve the problem.
That we solve the unfinished problem of Einstein’s.
That’s certainly the thing that I care about most in.
Hope for most.
Let me say one thing.
Among the young people that I work with,
I hear very often and sense a total disinterest
in these arguments that we older scientists have.
And an interest in what each other is doing.
And this is starting to appear in conferences
where the young people interested in quantum gravity
make a conference, they invite loops and strings
and causal dynamical triangulations and causal set people.
And we’re having a conference like this next week,
a small workshop at perimeter.
And I guess I’m advertising this.
And then in the summer,
we’re having a big full on conference,
which is just quantum gravity.
It’s not strings, it’s not loops.
But the organizers and the speakers
will be from all the different communities.
And this to me is very helpful.
That the different ideas are coming together.
At least people are expressing an interest in that.
It’s a huge honor talking to you, Lee.
Thanks so much for your time today.
Thank you.
Thanks for listening to this conversation.
And thank you to our presenting sponsor, Cash App.
Download it, use code LexPodcast.
You’ll get $10 and $10 will go to FIRST,
an organization that inspires and educates young minds
to become science and technology innovators of tomorrow.
If you enjoy this podcast, subscribe on YouTube,
give it five stars on Apple Podcast,
follow on Spotify, support it on Patreon,
or simply connect with me on Twitter at Lex Friedman.
And now let me leave you with some words from Lee Smolin.
One possibility is God is nothing but
the power of the universe to organize itself.
Thanks for listening and hope to see you next time.