The following is a conversation with Stephen Wolfram, a computer scientist, mathematician,
and theoretical physicist who is the founder and CEO of Wolfram Research, a company behind
Mathematica, Wolfram Alpha, Wolfram Language, and the new Wolfram Physics Project. He’s the author
of several books including A New Kind of Science, which on a personal note was one of the most
influential books in my journey in computer science and artificial intelligence. It made
me fall in love with the mathematical beauty and power of cellular automata.
It is true that perhaps one of the criticisms of Stephen is on a human level, that he has a big
ego, which prevents some researchers from fully enjoying the content of his ideas.
We talk about this point in this conversation. To me, ego can lead you astray but can also be
a superpower, one that fuels bold, innovative thinking that refuses to surrender to the cautious
ways of academic institutions. And here, especially, I ask you to join me in looking
past the peculiarities of human nature and opening your mind to the beauty of ideas in Stephen’s work
and in this conversation. I believe Stephen Wolfram is one of the most original minds of our time
and, at the core, is a kind, curious, and brilliant human being. This conversation was recorded in
November 2019 when the Wolfram Physics Project was underway but not yet ready for public
exploration as it is now. We now agreed to talk again, probably multiple times in the near future,
so this is round one, and stay tuned for round two soon.
This is the Artificial Intelligence Podcast. If you enjoy it, subscribe on YouTube,
review it with 5 Stars and Apple Podcast, support it on Patreon, or simply connect with me on Twitter
at Lex Friedman spelled F R I D M A N. As usual, I’ll do a few minutes of ads now and never any
ads in the middle that can break the flow of the conversation. I hope that works for you and
doesn’t hurt the listening experience. Quick summary of the ads. Two sponsors,
ExpressVPN and Cash App. Please consider supporting the podcast by getting ExpressVPN
at expressvpn.com slash lexpod and downloading Cash App and using code lexpodcast.
This show is presented by Cash App, the number one finance app in the App Store. When you get it,
use code lexpodcast. Cash App lets you send money to friends, buy Bitcoin, and invest in the stock
market with as little as one dollar. Since Cash App does fractional share trading, let me mention
that the order execution algorithm that works behind the scenes to create the abstraction of
fractional orders is an algorithmic marvel. So big props to the Cash App engineers for
solving a hard problem that in the end provides an easy interface that takes a step up to the
next layer of abstraction over the stock market. This makes trading more accessible for new
investors and diversification much easier. So again, if you get Cash App from the App Store,
Google Play, and use the code lexpodcast, you get ten dollars and Cash App will also donate
ten dollars to FIRST, an organization that is helping to advance robotics and STEM education
for young people around the world. This show is presented by ExpressVPN. Get it at expressvpn.com
slash lexpod to get a discount and to support this podcast. I’ve been using ExpressVPN for many years.
I love it. It’s really easy to use. Press the big power on button and your privacy is protected.
And if you like, you can make it look like your location is anywhere else in the world.
This has a large number of obvious benefits. Certainly, it allows you to access international
versions of streaming websites like the Japanese Netflix or the UK Hulu. ExpressVPN works on any
device you can imagine. I use it on Linux. Shout out to Ubuntu. New version coming out soon actually.
Windows, Android, but it’s available anywhere else too. Once again, get it at expressvpn.com
slash lexpod to get a discount and to support this podcast. And now here’s my conversation
with Stephen Wolfram. You and your son Christopher helped create the alien language in the movie
Arrival. So let me ask maybe a bit of a crazy question, but if aliens were to visit us on earth,
do you think we would be able to find a common language?
Well, by the time we’re saying aliens are visiting us, we’ve already prejudiced the whole story
because the concept of an alien actually visiting, so to speak, we already know they’re kind of
things that make sense to talk about visiting. So we already know they exist in the same kind
of physical setup that we do. It’s not just radio signals. It’s an actual thing that shows up and so
on. So I think in terms of can one find ways to communicate? Well, the best example we have of
this right now is AI. I mean, that’s our first sort of example of alien intelligence. And the
question is, how well do we communicate with AI? If you were in the middle of a neural network,
a neural net, and you open it up and it’s like, what are you thinking? Can you discuss things
with it? It’s not easy, but it’s not absolutely impossible. So I think by the time, given the
setup of your question, aliens visiting, I think the answer is yes, one will be able to find some
form of communication, whatever communication means. Communication requires notions of purpose
and things like this. It’s a kind of philosophical quagmire.
So if AI is a kind of alien life form, what do you think visiting looks like? So if we look at
aliens visiting, and we’ll get to discuss computation and the world of computation,
but if you were to imagine, you said you already prejudiced something by saying you visit,
but how would aliens visit?
By visit, there’s kind of an implication. And here we’re using the imprecision of human language,
you know, in a world of the future. And if that’s represented in computational language,
we might be able to take the concept visit and go look in the documentation, basically,
and find out exactly what does that mean, what properties does it have, and so on.
But by visit, in ordinary human language, I’m kind of taking it to be there’s something,
a physical embodiment that shows up in a spacecraft, since we kind of know that that’s
necessary. We’re not imagining it’s just, you know, photons showing up in a radio signal that,
you know, photons in some very elaborate pattern, we’re imagining it’s physical
things made of atoms and so on, that show up.
Can it be photons in a pattern?
Well, that’s a good question. I mean, whether there is the possibility,
you know, what counts as intelligence? Good question. I mean, it’s, you know, and I
used to think there was sort of a, oh, there’ll be, you know, it’ll be clear what it means to
find extraterrestrial intelligence, et cetera, et cetera, et cetera. I’ve increasingly realized,
as a result of science that I’ve done, that there really isn’t a bright line between
the intelligent and the merely computational, so to speak.
So, you know, in our kind of everyday sort of discussion, we’ll say things like, you know,
the weather has a mind of its own. Well, let’s unpack that question. You know, we realize
that there are computational processes that go on that determine the fluid dynamics of this and
that and the atmosphere, et cetera, et cetera, et cetera. How do we distinguish that from
the processes that go on in our brains of, you know, the physical processes that go on in our
brains? How do we separate those? How do we say the physical processes going on that represent
sophisticated computations in the weather, oh, that’s not the same as the physical processes
that go on that represent sophisticated computations in our brains? The answer is,
I don’t think there is a fundamental distinction. I think the distinction for us is that there’s
kind of a thread of history and so on that connects kind of what happens in different brains
to each other, so to speak. And it’s a, you know, what happens in the weather is something which is
not connected by sort of a thread of civilizational history, so to speak, to what we’re used to.
SL. In the stories that the human brains told us, but maybe the weather has its own stories.
MG. Absolutely. Absolutely. And that’s where we run into trouble thinking about extraterrestrial
intelligence because, you know, it’s like that pulsar magnetosphere that’s generating these very
elaborate radio signals. You know, is that something that we should think of as being this
whole civilization that’s developed over the last however long, you know, millions of years of
processes going on in the neutron star or whatever versus what, you know, what we’re used to in human
intelligence? I mean, I think in the end, you know, when people talk about extraterrestrial
intelligence and where is it and the whole, you know, Fermi paradox of how come there’s no other
signs of intelligence in the universe, my guess is that we’ve got sort of two alien forms of
intelligence that we’re dealing with, artificial intelligence and sort of physical or extraterrestrial
intelligence. And my guess is people will sort of get comfortable with the fact that both of these
have been achieved around the same time. And in other words, people will say, well, yes, we’re
used to computers, things we’ve created, digital things we’ve created, being sort of intelligent
like we are. And they’ll say, oh, we’re kind of also used to the idea that there are things around
the universe that are kind of intelligent like we are, except they don’t share the sort of
civilizational history that we have. And so they’re a different branch. I mean, it’s similar to when
you talk about life, for instance. I mean, you kind of said life form, I think almost synonymously
with intelligence, which I don’t think is, you know, the AIs would be upset to hear you equate
those two things. Because I really probably implied biological life. But you’re saying,
I mean, we’ll explore this more, but you’re saying it’s really a spectrum and it’s all just
a kind of computation. And so it’s a full spectrum and we just make ourselves special by weaving a
narrative around our particular kinds of computation. Yes. I mean, the thing that I think I’ve kind of
come to realize is, you know, at some level, it’s a little depressing to realize that there’s so
little or liberating. Well, yeah, but I mean, it’s, you know, it’s the story of science,
right? And, you know, from Copernicus on, it’s like, you know, first we were like,
convinced our planets at the center of the universe. No, that’s not true. Well, then we
were convinced there’s something very special about the chemistry that we have as biological
organisms. That’s not really true. And then we’re still holding out that hope. Oh, this intelligence
thing we have, that’s really special. I don’t think it is. However, in a sense, as you say,
it’s kind of liberating for the following reason, that you realize that what’s special is the
details of us, not some abstract attribute that, you know, we could wonder, oh, is something else
going to come along and, you know, also have that abstract attribute? Well, yes, every abstract
attribute we have, something else has it. But the full details of our kind of history of our
civilization and so on, nothing else has that. That’s what, you know, that’s our story, so to
speak. And that’s sort of almost by definition, special. So I view it as not being such a, I mean,
initially I was like, this is bad. This is kind of, you know, how can we have self respect about
the things that we do? Then I realized the details of the things we do, they are the story.
Everything else is kind of a blank canvas. So maybe on a small tangent, you just made me
think of it, but what do you make of the monoliths in 2001 Space Odyssey in terms of
aliens communicating with us and sparking the kind of particular intelligent computation that
we humans have? Is there anything interesting to get from that sci fi? Yeah, I mean, I think what’s
fun about that is, you know, the monoliths are these, you know, one to four to nine perfect
cuboid things. And in the Earth a million years ago, whatever they were portraying with a bunch
of apes and so on, a thing that has that level of perfection seems out of place. It seems very kind
of constructed, very engineered. So that’s an interesting question. What is the, you know,
what’s the techno signature, so to speak? What is it that you see it somewhere and you say,
my gosh, that had to be engineered. Now, the fact is we see crystals, which are also very perfect.
And, you know, the perfect ones are very perfect. They’re nice polyhedral or whatever.
And so in that sense, if you say, well, it’s a sign of sort of it’s a techno signature that
it’s a perfect polygonal shape, polyhedral shape. That’s not true. And so then it’s an interesting
question. What is the right signature? I mean, like, you know, Gauss, famous mathematician,
you know, he had this idea, you should cut down the Siberian forest in the shape of sort of a
typical image of the proof of the Pythagorean theorem on the grounds that it was a kind of
cool idea, didn’t get done. But, you know, it’s on the grounds that the Martians would see that and
realize, gosh, there are mathematicians out there. It’s kind of, you know, in his theory of the world,
that was probably the best advertisement for the cultural achievements of our species.
But, you know, it’s a reasonable question. What do you, what can you send or create that is a sign
of intelligence in its creation or even intention in its creation? You talk about if we were to send
a beacon. Can you what should we send? Is math our greatest creation? Is what is our greatest
creation? I think I think it’s a it’s a philosophically doomed issue. I mean, in other
words, you send something, you think it’s fantastic, but it’s kind of like we are part of
the universe. We make things that are, you know, things that happen in the universe.
Computation, which is sort of the thing that we are in some abstract sense using to create all
these elaborate things we create, is surprisingly ubiquitous. In other words, we might have thought
that, you know, we’ve built this whole giant engineering stack that’s led us to microprocessors,
that’s led us to be able to do elaborate computations. But this idea that computations
are happening all over the place. The only question is whether whether there’s a thread that connects
our human intentions to what those computations are. And so I think I think this question of what
do you send to kind of show off our civilization in the best possible way? I think any kind of
almost random slab of stuff we’ve produced is about equivalent to everything else. I think
it’s one of these things where it’s a non romantic way of phrasing it. I just started to interrupt,
but I just talked to Andrew in who’s the wife of Carl Sagan. And so I don’t know if you’re
familiar with the Voyager. I mean, she was part of sending, I think, brainwaves of, you know,
wasn’t it hers? Her brainwaves when she was first falling in love with Carl Sagan. It’s
this beautiful story that perhaps you would shut down the power of that by saying we might
as well send anything else. And that’s interesting. All of it is kind of an interesting, peculiar
thing. Yeah, yeah, right. Well, I mean, I think it’s kind of interesting to see on the Voyager,
you know, golden record thing. One of the things that’s kind of cute about that is, you know,
it was made when was it in the late 70s, early 80s. And, you know, one of the things, it’s a
phonograph record. Okay. And it has a diagram of how to play a phonograph record. And, you know,
it’s kind of like it’s shocking that in just 30 years, if you show that to a random kid of today,
and you show them that diagram, I’ve tried this experiment, they’re like, I don’t know what the
heck this is. And the best anybody can think of is, you know, take the whole record, forget the
fact that it has some kind of helical track in it, just image the whole thing and see what’s there.
That’s what we would do today. In only 30 years, our technology has kind of advanced to the point
where the playing of a helical, you know, mechanical track on a phonograph record is now
something bizarre. So, you know, it’s a cautionary tale, I would say, in terms of the ability to make
something that in detail sort of leads by the nose, some, you know, the aliens or whatever,
to do something. It’s like, no, you know, best you can do, as I say, if we were doing this today,
we would not build a helical scan thing with a needle. We would just take some high resolution
imaging system and get all the bits off it and say, oh, it’s a big nuisance that they put in a
helix, you know, in a spiral. Let’s just unravel the spiral and start from there.
SL. Do you think, and this will get into trying to figure out interpretability of AI,
interpretability of computation, being able to communicate with various kinds of computations,
do you think we’d be able to, if you put your alien hat on, figure out this record,
how to play this record?
MG. Well, it’s a question of what one wants to do. I mean,
SL. Understand what the other party was trying to communicate or understand anything about the
other party.
MG. What does understanding mean? I mean, that’s the issue. The issue is, it’s like when people
were trying to do natural language understanding for computers, right? So people tried to do that
for years. It wasn’t clear what it meant. In other words, you take your piece of English or whatever,
and you say, gosh, my computer has understood this. Okay, that’s nice. What can you do with that?
Well, so for example, when we built WolfMalpha, one of the things was it’s doing question answering
and so on, and it needs to do natural language understanding. The reason that I realized after
the fact, the reason we were able to do natural language understanding quite well, and people
hadn’t before, the number one thing was we had an actual objective for the natural language
understanding. We were trying to turn the natural language into this computational language
that we could then do things with. Now, similarly, when you imagine your alien, you say,
okay, we’re playing them the record. Did they understand it? Well, it depends what you mean.
If there’s a representation that they have, if it converts to some representation where we can say,
oh yes, that’s a representation that we can recognize is represents understanding, then all
well and good. But actually, the only ones that I think we can say would represent understanding
are ones that will then do things that we humans kind of recognize as being useful to us.
Maybe you’re trying to understand, quantify how technologically advanced this particular
civilization is. So are they a threat to us from a military perspective? That’s probably the
first kind of understanding they’ll be interested in. Gosh, that’s so hard. That’s like in the
Arrival movie, that was one of the key questions is, why are you here, so to speak? Are you going
to hurt us? But even that, it’s very unclear. It’s like, are you going to hurt us? That comes
back to a lot of interesting AI ethics questions, because we might make an AI that says, well,
take autonomous cars, for instance. Are you going to hurt us? Well, let’s make sure you only drive
at precisely the speed limit, because we want to make sure we don’t hurt you, so to speak.
But you say, but actually, that means I’m going to be really late for this thing, and
that sort of hurts me in some way. So it’s hard to know. Even the definition of what it means to
hurt someone is unclear. And as we start thinking about things about AI ethics and so on, that’s
something one has to address. There’s always tradeoffs, and that’s the annoying thing about
ethics. Yeah, well, right. And I think ethics, like these other things we’re talking about,
is a deeply human thing. There’s no abstract, let’s write down the theorem that proves that
this is ethically correct. That’s a meaningless idea. You have to have a ground truth, so to
speak, that’s ultimately what humans want, and they don’t all want the same thing. So that gives
one all kinds of additional complexity in thinking about that. One convenient thing in terms of
turning ethics into computation, you can ask the question of what maximizes the likelihood of the
survival of the species. That’s a good existential issue. But then when you say survival of the
species, you might say, you might, for example, let’s say, forget about technology, just hang out
and be happy, live our lives, go on to the next generation, go through many, many generations
where, in a sense, nothing is happening. Is that okay? Is that not okay? Hard to know. In terms of
the attempt to do elaborate things and the attempt to might be counterproductive for the survival of
the species. It’s also a little bit hard to know, so okay, let’s take that as a sort of thought
experiment. You can say, well, what are the threats that we might have to survive? The
super volcano, the asteroid impact, all these kinds of things. Okay, so now we inventory these
possible threats and we say, let’s make our species as robust as possible relative to all
these threats. I think in the end, it’s sort of an unknowable thing what it takes. So given that
you’ve got this AI and you’ve told it, maximize the long term. What does long term mean? Does
long term mean until the sun burns out? That’s not going to work. Does long term mean next thousand
years? Okay, they’re probably optimizations for the next thousand years. It’s like if you’re
running a company, you can make a company be very stable for a certain period of time.
Like if your company gets bought by some private investment group, then you can run a company just
fine for five years by just taking what it does and removing all R&D and the company will burn
out after a while, but it’ll run just fine for a little while. So if you tell the AI, keep the
humans okay for a thousand years, there’s probably a certain set of things that one would do to
optimize that, many of which one might say, well, that would be a pretty big shame for the future of
history, so to speak, for that to be what happens. But I think in the end, as you start thinking
about that question, what you realize is there’s a whole sort of raft of undecidability, computational
irreducibility. In other words, one of the good things about what our civilization has gone
through and what we humans go through is that there’s a certain computational irreducibility
to it in the sense that it isn’t the case that you can look from the outside and just say,
the answer is going to be this. At the end of the day, this is what’s going to happen.
You actually have to go through the process to find out. And I think that feels better in the
sense that something is achieved by going through all of this process. But it also means
that telling the AI, go figure out what will be the best outcome. Well, unfortunately, it’s going
to come back and say, it’s kind of undecidable what to do. We’d have to run all of those scenarios
to see what happens. And if we want it for the infinite future, we’re thrown immediately into
sort of standard issues of kind of infinite computation and so on. So yeah, even if you
get that the answer to the universe and everything is 42, you still have to actually run the universe.
Yes, to figure out the question, I guess, or the journey is the point.
Right. Well, I think it’s saying to summarize, this is the result of the universe. If that is
possible, it tells us, I mean, the whole sort of structure of thinking about computation and so on
and thinking about how stuff works. If it’s possible to say, and the answer is such and such,
you’re basically saying there’s a way of going outside the universe. And you’re getting yourself
into something of a sort of paradox because you’re saying, if it’s knowable what the answer is, then
there’s a way to know it that is beyond what the universe provides. But if we can know it, then
something that we’re dealing with is beyond the universe. So then the universe isn’t the universe,
so to speak. And in general, as we’ll talk about, at least for our small human brains, it’s
hard to show the result of a sufficiently complex computation. I mean, it’s probably impossible,
right, on this side ability. And the universe appears by at least the poets to be sufficiently
complex. They won’t be able to predict what the heck it’s all going to. Well, we better not be
able to, because if we can, it kind of denies. I mean, it’s you know, we’re part of the universe.
Yeah. So what does it mean for us to predict? It means that we that our little part of the universe
is able to jump ahead of the whole universe. And this this quickly winds up. I mean, that it is
conceivable. The only way we’d be able to predict is if we are so special in the universe, we are
the one place where there is computation more special, more sophisticated than anything else
that exists in the universe. That’s the only way we would have the ability to sort of the almost
theological ability, so to speak, to predict what happens in the universe is to say somehow we’re
better than everything else in the universe, which I don’t think is the case. Yeah, perhaps we can
detect a large number of looping patterns that reoccur throughout the universe and fully describe
them. And therefore, but then it still becomes exceptionally difficult to see how those patterns
interact and what kind of well, look, the most remarkable thing about the universe is that it’s
has regularity at all. Might not be the case. If you just have regularity, do you? Absolutely.
That fits full of I mean, physics is successful. You know, it’s full of of laws that tell us a lot
of detail about how the universe works. I mean, it could be the case that, you know, the 10 to the
90th particles in the universe, they will do their own thing, but they don’t. They all follow. We
already know they all follow basically physical, the same physical laws. And that’s something
that’s a very profound fact about the universe. What conclusion you draw from that is unclear. I
mean, in the, you know, the early early theologians, that was, you know, exhibit number one for the
existence of God. Now, you know, people have different conclusions about it. But the fact is,
you know, right now, I mean, I happen to be interested, actually, I’ve just restarted a
long running kind of interest of mine about fundamental physics. I’m kind of like, come on,
I’m on a bit of a quest, which I’m about to make more public, to see if I can actually find the
fundamental theory of physics. Excellent. We’ll come to that. And I just had a lot of conversations
with quantum mechanics folks with so I’m really excited on your take, because I think you have a
fascinating take on the the fundamental nature of our reality from a physics perspective. So
and what might be underlying the kind of physics as we think of it today. Okay, let’s take a step
back. What is computation? It’s a good question. Operationally, computation is following rules.
That’s kind of it. I mean, computation is the result is the process of systematically following
rules. And it is the thing that happens when you do that. So taking initial conditions are taking
inputs and following rules. I mean, what are you following rules on? So there has to be some data,
some unnecessarily, it can be something where there’s a, you know, very simple input. And then
you’re following these rules. And you’d say there’s not really much data going into this.
It’s you could actually pack the initial conditions into the rule, if you want to. So I think the
question is, is there a robust notion of computation? That is, what does robust mean?
What I mean by that is something like this. So So one of the things in a different in another
physics, something like energy, okay, the different forms of energy, there’s, but somehow energy is a
robust concept that doesn’t, isn’t particular to kinetic energy, or, you know, nuclear energy,
or whatever else, there’s a robust idea of energy. So one of the things you might ask is,
is the robust idea of computation? Or does it matter that this computation is running in a
Turing machine? This computation is running in a, you know, CMOS, silicon, CPU, this computation is
running in a fluid system in the weather, those kinds of things? Or is there a robust idea of
computation that transcends the sort of detailed framework that it’s running in? Okay. And is there?
Yes. I mean, it wasn’t obvious that there was. So it’s worth understanding the history and how we
got to where we are right now. Because, you know, to say that there is, is a statement in part about
our universe. It’s not a statement about what is mathematically conceivable. It’s about what
actually can exist for us. Maybe you can also comment because energy, as a concept is robust.
But there’s also its intricate, complicated relationship with matter, with mass, is very
interesting, of particles that carry force and particles that sort of particles that carry force
and particles that have mass. These kinds of ideas, they seem to map to each other, at least
in the mathematical sense. Is there a connection between energy and mass and computation? Or are
these completely disjoint ideas? We don’t know yet. The things that I’m trying to do about fundamental
physics may well lead to such a connection, but there is no known connection at this time.
So can you elaborate a little bit more on what, how do you think about computation? What is
computation? What is computation? Yeah. So I mean, let’s, let’s tell a little bit of a historical
story. Okay. So, you know, back, go back 150 years, people were making mechanical calculators of
various kinds. And, you know, the typical thing was you want an adding machine, you go to the
adding machine store, basically, you want a multiplying machine, you go to the multiplying
machine store, they’re different pieces of hardware. And so that means that, at least at the
level of that kind of computation, and those kinds of pieces of hardware, there isn’t a robust notion
of computation, there’s the adding machine kind of computation, there’s the multiplying machine
notion of computation, and they’re disjoint. So what happened in around 1900, people started
imagining, particularly in the context of mathematical logic, could you have something
which would be represent any reasonable function, right? And they came up with things, this idea of
primitive recursion was one of the early ideas. And it didn’t work. There were reasonable functions
that people could come up with that were not represented using the primitives of primitive
recursion. Okay, so then, then along comes 1931, and Godel’s theorem, and so on. And as in looking
back, one can see that as part of the process of establishing Godel’s theorem, Godel basically
showed how you could compile arithmetic, how you could basically compile logical statements like
this statement is unprovable into arithmetic. So what he essentially did was to show that
arithmetic can be a computer in a sense that’s capable of representing all kinds of other things.
And then Turing came along 1936, came up with Turing machines. Meanwhile, Alonzo Church had
come up with lambda calculus. And the surprising thing that was established very quickly is the
Turing machine idea about what might be what computation might be is exactly the same as the
lambda calculus idea of what computation might be. And so, and then there started to be other ideas,
you know, register machines, other kinds of other kinds of representations of computation.
And the big surprise was, they all turned out to be equivalent. So in other words, it might have
been the case, like those old adding machines and multiplying machines, that, you know, Turing had
his idea of computation, Church had his idea of computation, and they were just different. But it
isn’t true. They’re actually all equivalent. So then by, I would say the 1970s or so in sort of
the computation, computer science, computation theory area, people had sort of said, oh,
Turing machines are kind of what computation is. Physicists were still holding out saying, no,
no, no, that’s just not how the universe works. We’ve got all these differential equations.
We’ve got all these real numbers that have infinite numbers of digits.
The universe is not a Turing machine.
Right. The, you know, the Turing machines are a small subset of the things that we make in
microprocessors and engineering structures and so on. So probably actually through my work in the
1980s about sort of the relationship between computation and models of physics, it became a
little less clear that there would be, that there was this big sort of dichotomy between what can
happen in physics and what happens in things like Turing machines. And I think probably by now people
would mostly think, and by the way, brains were another kind of element of this. I mean, you know,
Gödel didn’t think that his notion of computation or what amounted to his notion of computation
would cover brains. And Turing wasn’t sure either. But although he was a little bit,
he got to be a little bit more convinced that it should cover brains. But I would say by probably
sometime in the 1980s, there was beginning to be sort of a general belief that yes, this notion
of computation that could be captured by things like Turing machines was reasonably robust.
Now, the next question is, okay, you can have a universal Turing machine that’s capable of
being programmed to do anything that any Turing machine can do. And, you know, this idea of
universal computation, it’s an important idea, this idea that you can have one piece of hardware
and program it with different pieces of software. You know, that’s kind of the idea that launched
most modern technology. I mean, that’s kind of, that’s the idea that launched computer revolution
software, etc. So important idea. But the thing that’s still kind of holding out from that idea
is, okay, there is this universal computation thing, but seems hard to get to. It seems like
you want to make a universal computer, you have to kind of have a microprocessor with, you know,
a million gates in it, and you have to go to a lot of trouble to make something that achieves that
level of computational sophistication. Okay, so the surprise for me was that stuff that I discovered
in the early 80s, looking at these things called cellular automata, which are really simple
computational systems, the thing that was a big surprise to me was that even when their rules were
very, very simple, they were doing things that were as sophisticated as they did when their rules
were much more complicated. So it didn’t look like, you know, this idea, oh, to get sophisticated
computation, you have to build something with very sophisticated rules. That idea didn’t seem to pan
out. And instead, it seemed to be the case that sophisticated computation was completely ubiquitous,
even in systems with incredibly simple rules. And so that led to this thing that I call the
principle of computational equivalence, which basically says, when you have a system that
follows rules of any kind, then whenever the system isn’t doing things that are, in some sense,
obviously simple, then the computation that the behavior of the system corresponds to is of
equivalence sophistication. So that means that when you kind of go from the very, very, very
simplest things you can imagine, then quite quickly, you hit this kind of threshold above
which everything is equivalent in its computational sophistication. Not obvious that would be the case.
I mean, that’s a science fact. Well, no, hold on a second. So this you’ve opened with a new kind
of science. I mean, I remember it was a huge eye opener that such simple things can create such
complexity. And yes, there’s an equivalence, but it’s not a fact. It just appears to, I mean,
it’s as much as a fact as sort of these theories are so elegant that it seems to be the way things
are. But let me ask sort of, you just brought up previously, kind of like the communities of
computer scientists with their Turing machines, the physicists with their universe, and whoever
the heck, maybe neuroscientists looking at the brain. What’s your sense in the equivalence?
You’ve shown through your work that simple rules can create equivalently complex Turing machine
systems, right? Is the universe equivalent to the kinds of Turing machines? Is the human brain
a kind of Turing machine? Do you see those things basically blending together? Or is there still a
mystery about how disjoint they are? Well, my guess is that they all blend together, but we don’t know
that for sure yet. I mean, this, you know, I should say, I said rather glibly that the principle of
computational equivalence is sort of a science fact. And I was using air quotes for the science fact,
because when you, it is a, I mean, just to talk about that for a second. The thing is that it has
a complicated epistemological character, similar to things like the second law of thermodynamics,
the law of entropy increase. What is the second law of thermodynamics? Is it a law of nature? Is
it a thing that is true of the physical world? Is it something which is mathematically provable? Is
it something which happens to be true of the systems that we see in the world? Is it, in some
sense, a definition of heat, perhaps? Well, it’s a combination of those things. And it’s the same
thing with the principle of computational equivalence. And in some sense, the principle
of computational equivalence is at the heart of the definition of computation, because it’s telling
you there is a thing, there is a robust notion that is equivalent across all these systems and
doesn’t depend on the details of each individual system. And that’s why we can meaningfully talk
about a thing called computation. And we’re not stuck talking about, oh, there’s computation in
Turing machine number 3785, and et cetera, et cetera, et cetera. That’s why there is a robust
notion like that. Now, on the other hand, can we prove the principle of computational equivalence?
Can we prove it as a mathematical result? Well, the answer is, actually, we’ve got some nice results
along those lines that say, throw me a random system with very simple rules. Well, in a couple
of cases, we now know that even the very simplest rules we can imagine of a certain type are
universal and do follow what you would expect from the principle of computational equivalence. So
that’s a nice piece of sort of mathematical evidence for the principle of computational equivalence.
Just to link on that point, the simple rules creating sort of these complex behaviors. But
is there a way to mathematically say that this behavior is complex? That you’ve mentioned that
you cross a threshold. Right. So there are various indicators. So, for example, one thing would be,
is it capable of universal computation? That is, given the system, do there exist initial
conditions for the system that can be set up to essentially represent programs to do anything you
want, to compute primes, to compute pi, to do whatever you want? Right. So that’s an indicator.
So we know in a couple of examples that, yes, the simplest candidates that could conceivably have
that property do have that property. And that’s what the principle of computational equivalence
might suggest. But this principle of computational equivalence, one question about it is, is it true
for the physical world? It might be true for all these things we come up with, the Turing machines,
the cellular automata, whatever else. Is it true for our actual physical world? Is it true for the
brains, which are an element of the physical world? We don’t know for sure. And that’s not the
type of question that we will have a definitive answer to, because there’s a sort of scientific
induction issue. You can say, well, it’s true for all these brains, but this person over here is
really special, and it’s not true for them. And the only way that that cannot be what happens is
if we finally nail it and actually get a fundamental theory for physics, and it turns out
to correspond to, let’s say, a simple program. If that is the case, then we will basically have
reduced physics to a branch of mathematics, in the sense that we will not be, you know,
right now with physics, we’re like, well, this is the theory that, you know, this is the rules that
apply here. But in the middle of that, you know, right by that black hole, maybe these rules don’t
apply and something else applies. And there may be another piece of the onion that we have to peel
back. But if we can get to the point where we actually have, this is the fundamental theory of
physics, here it is, it’s this program, run this program, and you will get our universe, then we’ve
kind of reduced the problem of figuring out things in physics to a problem of doing some, what turns
out to be very difficult, irreducibly difficult, mathematical problems. But it no longer is the
case that we can say that somebody can come in and say, whoops, you know, you will write about
all these things about Turing machines, but you’re wrong about the physical universe, we know
there’s sort of ground truth about what’s happening in the physical universe. Now, I happen to think,
I mean, you asked me at an interesting time, because I’m just in the middle of starting to
to re energize my, my project to kind of study fundamental theory of physics. As of today, I’m
very optimistic that we’re actually going to find something and that it’s going to be possible to
to see that the universe really is computational in that sense. But I don’t know, because we’re
betting against, you know, we’re betting against the universe, so to speak. And I didn’t, you know,
it’s not like, you know, when I spend a lot of my life building technology, and then I know what
what’s in there, right? And it’s there may be, it may have unexpected behavior, may have bugs,
things like that. But fundamentally, I know what’s in there for the universe. I’m not in
that position, so to speak. What kind of computation do you think the fundamental laws of
physics might emerge from? Just to clarify, so you’ve done a lot of fascinating work with kind
of discrete kinds of computation that, you know, you can sell your automata, and we’ll talk about
it, have this very clean structures, it’s such a nice way to demonstrate that simple rules
can create immense complexity. But what kind, you know, is that actually, are cellular automata
sufficiently general to describe the kinds of computation that might create the laws of physics?
Just to give, can you give a sense of what kind of computation do you think would create?
Well, so this is a slightly complicated issue, because as soon as you have universal
computation, you can, in principle, simulate anything with anything.
Right. But it is not a natural thing to do. And if you’re asking, were you to try to find our
physical universe by looking at possible programs in the computational universe of all possible
programs, would the ones that correspond to our universe be small and simple enough that we might
find them by searching that computational universe? We got to have the right basis, so to speak. We
have to have the right language, in effect, for describing computation for that to be feasible.
So the thing that I’ve been interested in for a long time is, what are the most structuralist
structures that we can create with computation? So in other words, if you say a cellular automaton,
it has a bunch of cells that are arrayed on a grid, and it’s very, you know, and every cell is
updated in synchrony at a particular, you know, when there’s a click of a clock, so to speak,
and it goes a tick of a clock, and every cell gets updated at the same time. That’s a very specific
very rigid kind of thing. But my guess is that when we look at physics, and we look at things
like space and time, that what’s underneath space and time is something as structuralist as possible,
that what we see, what emerges for us as physical space, for example, comes from something that is
sort of arbitrarily unstructured underneath. And so I’ve been for a long time interested in kind
of what are the most structuralist structures that we can set up. And actually, what I had thought
about for ages is using graphs, networks, where essentially, so let’s talk about space, for
example. So what is space? It’s a kind of a question one might ask. Back in the early days
of quantum mechanics, for example, people said, oh, for sure, space is going to be discrete,
because all these other things we’re finding are discrete. But that never worked out in physics.
And so space in physics today is always treated as this continuous thing, just like Euclid
imagined it. I mean, the very first thing Euclid says in his sort of common notions is,
you know, a point is something which has no part. In other words, there are points that are
arbitrarily small, and there’s a continuum of possible positions of points. And the question
is, is that true? And so for example, if we look at, I don’t know, fluid like air or water,
we might say, oh, it’s a continuous fluid. We can pour it, we can do all kinds of things continuously.
But actually, we know, because we know the physics of it, that it consists of a bunch
of discrete molecules bouncing around, and only in the aggregate is it behaving like a continuum.
And so the possibility exists that that’s true of space too. People haven’t managed to make that
work with existing frameworks in physics. But I’ve been interested in whether one can imagine that
underneath space, and also underneath time, is something more structureless. And the question is,
is it computational? So there are a couple of possibilities. It could be computational,
somehow fundamentally equivalent to a Turing machine, or it could be fundamentally not. So
how could it not be? It could not be, so a Turing machine essentially deals with integers, whole
numbers, at some level. And you know, it can do things like it can add one to a number, it can do
things like this. And it can also store whatever the heck it did. Yes, it has an infinite storage.
But when one thinks about doing physics, or sort of idealized physics, or idealized mathematics,
one can deal with real numbers, numbers with an infinite number of digits, numbers which are
absolutely precise. And one can say, we can take this number and we can multiply it by itself.
Are you comfortable with infinity?
In this context? Are you comfortable in the context of computation? Do you think infinity
plays a part? I think that the role of infinity is complicated. Infinity is useful in conceptualizing
things. It’s not actualizable. Almost by definition, it’s not actualizable. But do you
think infinity is part of the thing that might underlie the laws of physics? I think that no.
I think there are many questions that you ask about, you might ask about physics, which inevitably
involve infinity. Like when you say, you know, is faster than light travel possible? You could say,
given the laws of physics, can you make something even arbitrarily large, even quote, infinitely
large, that will make faster than light travel possible? Then you’re thrown into dealing with
infinity as a kind of theoretical question. But I mean, talking about sort of what’s underneath
space and time and how one can make a computational infrastructure, one possibility is that you can’t
make a computational infrastructure in a Turing machine sense, that you really have to be dealing
with precise real numbers. You’re dealing with partial differential equations, which have
precise real numbers at arbitrarily closely separated points. You have a continuum for
everything. Could be that that’s what happens, that there’s sort of a continuum for everything
and precise real numbers for everything. And then the things I’m thinking about are wrong.
And that’s the risk you take if you’re trying to sort of do things about nature,
is you might just be wrong. For me personally, it’s kind of a strange thing. I’ve spent a lot
of my life building technology where you can do something that nobody cares about,
but you can’t be sort of wrong in that sense, in the sense you build your technology and it does
what it does. But I think this question of what the sort of underlying computational
infrastructure for the universe might be, it’s sort of inevitable it’s going to be fairly abstract,
because if you’re going to get all these things like there are three dimensions of space,
there are electrons, there are muons, there are quarks, there are this, you don’t get to,
if the model for the universe is simple, you don’t get to have sort of a line of code for
each of those things. You don’t get to have sort of the muon case, the tau lepton case and so on.
Because they all have to be emergent somehow, something deeper.
Right. So that means it’s sort of inevitable, it’s a little hard to talk about
what the sort of underlying structuralist structure actually is.
Do you think human beings have the cognitive capacity to understand, if we’re to discover it,
to understand the kinds of simple structure from which these laws can emerge?
Like, do you think that’s a good question?
Well, here’s what I think. I think that, I mean, I’m right in the middle of this right now.
Right.
I’m telling you that I think this, yeah, I mean, this human has a hard time understanding,
you know, a bunch of the things that are going on. But what happens in understanding is
one builds waypoints. I mean, if you said understand modern 21st century mathematics,
starting from, you know, counting back in, you know, whenever counting was invented 50,000 years
ago, whatever it was, right, that would be really difficult. But what happens is we build waypoints
that allow us to get to higher levels of understanding. And we see the same thing
happening in language. You know, when we invent a word for something, it provides kind of a cognitive
anchor, a kind of a waypoint that lets us, you know, like a podcast or something. You could be
explaining, well, it’s a thing which works this way, that way, the other way. But as soon as you
have the word podcast and people kind of societally understand it, you start to be able to build on
top of that. And so I think that’s kind of the story of science actually, too. I mean, science
is about building these kind of waypoints where we find this sort of cognitive mechanism for
understanding something, then we can build on top of it. You know, we have the idea of, I don’t
know, differential equations we can build on top of that. We have this idea, that idea. So my hope
is that if it is the case that we have to go all the way sort of from the sand to the computer,
and there’s no waypoints in between, then we’re toast. We won’t be able to do that.
Well, eventually we might. So if we’re as clever apes are good enough at building those abstract
abstractions, eventually from sand we’ll get to the computer, right? And it just might be a longer
journey. The question is whether it is something that you asked, whether our human brains will
quote, understand what’s going on. And that’s a different question because for that, it requires
steps from which we can construct a human understandable narrative. And that’s something that
I think I am somewhat hopeful that that will be possible. Although, you know, as of literally
today, if you ask me, I’m confronted with things that I don’t understand very well.
So this is a small pattern in a computation trying to understand the rules under which the
computation functions. And it’s an interesting possibility under which kinds of computations
such a creature can understand itself.
My guess is that within, so we didn’t talk much about computational irreducibility,
but it’s a consequence of this principle of computational equivalence. And it’s sort of a
core idea that one has to understand, I think, which is question is, you’re doing a computation,
you can figure out what happens in the computation just by running every step in the computation and
seeing what happens. Or you can say, let me jump ahead and figure out, you know, have something
smarter that figures out what’s going to happen before it actually happens. And a lot of traditional
science has been about that act of computational reducibility. It’s like, we’ve got these equations,
and we can just solve them, and we can figure out what’s going to happen. We don’t have to trace
all of those steps, we just jump ahead because we solve these equations.
Okay, so one of the things that is a consequence of the principle of computational equivalence is
you don’t always get to do that. Many, many systems will be computationally irreducible,
in the sense that the only way to find out what they do is just follow each step and see what
happens. Why is that? Well, if you’re saying, well, we, with our brains, we’re a lot smarter,
we don’t have to mess around like the little cellular automaton going through and updating
all those cells. We can just use the power of our brains to jump ahead. But if the principle
of computational equivalence is right, that’s not going to be correct, because it means that
there’s us doing our computation in our brains, there’s a little cellular automaton doing its
computation, and the principle of computational equivalence says these two computations are
fundamentally equivalent. So that means we don’t get to say we’re a lot smarter than the cellular
automaton and jump ahead, because we’re just doing computation that’s of the same sophistication as
the cellular automaton itself. That’s computational reducibility. It’s fascinating. And that’s a
really powerful idea. I think that’s both depressing and humbling and so on, that we’re all,
we and the cellular automaton are the same. But the question we’re talking about, the fundamental
laws of physics, is kind of the reverse question. You’re not predicting what’s going to happen. You
have to run the universe for that. But saying, can I understand what rules likely generated me?
I understand. But the problem is, to know whether you’re right, you have to have some
computational reducibility, because we are embedded in the universe. If the only way to know whether
we get the universe is just to run the universe, we don’t get to do that, because it just ran for
14.6 billion years or whatever. And we can’t rerun it, so to speak. So we have to hope that
there are pockets of computational reducibility sufficient to be able to say, yes, I can recognize
those are electrons there. And I think that it’s a feature of computational irreducibility. It’s
sort of a mathematical feature that there are always an infinite collection of pockets of
reducibility. The question of whether they land in the right place and whether we can sort of build
a theory based on them is unclear. But to this point about whether we as observers in the universe
built out of the same stuff as the universe can figure out the universe, so to speak, that relies
on these pockets of reducibility. Without the pockets of reducibility, it won’t work, can’t work.
But I think this question about how observers operate, it’s one of the features of science over
the last 100 years particularly, has been that every time we get more realistic about observers,
we learn a bit more about science. So for example, relativity was all about observers don’t get to
say what’s simultaneous with what. They have to just wait for the light signal to arrive to decide
what’s simultaneous. Or for example, in thermodynamics, observers don’t get to say the
position of every single molecule in a gas. They can only see the kind of large scale features,
and that’s why the second law of thermodynamics, the law of entropy increase, and so on works.
If you could see every individual molecule, you wouldn’t conclude something about thermodynamics.
You would conclude, oh, these molecules are just all doing these particular things. You wouldn’t
be able to see this aggregate fact. So I strongly expect that, and in fact, in the theories that I
have, that one has to be more realistic about the computation and other aspects of observers
in order to actually make a correspondence between what we experience. In fact,
my little team and I have a little theory right now about how quantum mechanics may work, which is
a very wonderfully bizarre idea about how the sort of thread of human consciousness
relates to what we observe in the universe. But there’s several steps to explain what that’s
about. What do you make of the mess of the observer at the lower level of quantum mechanics,
sort of the textbook definition with quantum mechanics kind of says that there’s some,
there’s two worlds. One is the world that actually is, and the other is that’s observed.
What do you make sense of that? Well, I think actually the ideas we’ve recently had might
actually give away into this. I don’t know yet. I think it’s a mess. The fact is,
one of the things that’s interesting, and when people look at these models that I
started talking about 30 years ago now, they say, oh no, that can’t possibly be right.
What about quantum mechanics? You say, okay, tell me what is the essence of quantum mechanics? What
do you want me to be able to reproduce to know that I’ve got quantum mechanics, so to speak?
Well, and that question comes up. It comes up very operationally actually, because we’ve been
doing a bunch of stuff with quantum computing. And there are all these companies that say,
we have a quantum computer. And we say, let’s connect to your API and let’s actually run it.
And they’re like, well, maybe you shouldn’t do that yet. We’re not quite ready yet.
And one of the questions that I’ve been curious about is, if I have five minutes with a quantum
computer, how can I tell if it’s really a quantum computer or whether it’s a simulator at the other
end? And it turns out it’s really hard. It’s like a lot of these questions about what is
intelligence? What’s life? It’s like, are you really a quantum computer? Yes, exactly. Is it
just a simulation or is it really a quantum computer? Same issue all over again. So this
whole issue about the sort of mathematical structure of quantum mechanics and the completely
separate thing that is our experience in which we think definite things happen, whereas quantum
mechanics doesn’t say definite things ever happen. Quantum mechanics is all about the amplitudes for
different things to happen, but yet our thread of consciousness operates as if definite things
are happening. Dilinga, on the point, you’ve kind of mentioned the structure that could
underlie everything and this idea that it could perhaps have something like a structure of a graph.
Can you elaborate why your intuition is that there’s a graph structure of nodes and edges
and what it might represent? Right. Okay. So the question is, what is, in a sense,
the most structuralist structure you can imagine, right? And in fact, what I’ve recently realized
in the last year or so, I have a new most structuralist structure. By the way, the question
itself is a beautiful one and a powerful one in itself. So even without an answer, just the
question is a really strong question. Right. But what’s your new idea? Well, it has to do with
hypergraphs. Essentially, what is interesting about the sort of model I have now is it’s a
little bit like what happened with computation. Everything that I think of as, oh, well, maybe
the model is this, I discover it’s equivalent. And that’s quite encouraging because it’s like
I could say, well, I’m going to look at trivalent graphs with three edges for each node and so on,
or I could look at this special kind of graph, or I could look at this kind of algebraic structure.
And turns out that the things I’m now looking at, everything that I’ve imagined that is a plausible
type of structuralist structure is equivalent to this. So what is it? Well, a typical way to think
about it is, well, so you might have some collection of tuples, collection of, let’s say,
numbers. So you might have one, three, five, two, three, four, just collections of numbers,
triples of numbers, let’s say, quadruples of numbers, pairs of numbers, whatever.
And you have all these sort of floating little tuples. They’re not in any particular order.
And that sort of floating collection of tuples, and I told you this was abstract,
represents the whole universe. The only thing that relates them is when a symbol is the same,
it’s the same, so to speak. So if you have two tuples and they contain the same symbol,
let’s say at the same position of the tuple, at the first element of the tuple,
then that represents a relation. So let me try and peel this back.
Wow. Okay.
I told you it’s abstract, but this is the…
So the relationship is formed by some aspect of sameness.
Right. But so think about it in terms of a graph. So a graph, a bunch of nodes,
let’s say you number each node, then what is a graph? A graph is a set of pairs that say
this node has an edge connecting it to this other node. And a graph is just a collection
of those pairs that say this node connects to this other node. So this is a generalization of that,
in which instead of having pairs, you have arbitrary n tuples. That’s it. That’s the
whole story. And now the question is, okay, so that might represent the state of the universe.
How does the universe evolve? What does the universe do? And so the answer is
that what I’m looking at is a transformation rules on these hypergraphs. In other words,
you say this, whenever you see a piece of this hypergraph that looks like this,
turn it into a piece of hypergraph that looks like this. So on a graph, it might be when you
see the subgraph, when you see this thing with a bunch of edges hanging out in this particular way,
then rewrite it as this other graph. Okay. And so that’s the whole story. So the question is
what, uh, so now you say, I mean, as I say, this is quite abstract. And one of the questions is,
uh, where do you do those updating? So you’ve got this giant graph. What triggers the updating,
like what’s the, what’s the ripple effect of it? Is it, uh, and I suspect everything’s discreet
even in time. So, okay. So the question is where do you do the updates? And the answer is the rule
is you do them wherever they apply. And you do them, you do them. The order in which the updates
is done is not defined. That is the, you can do them. So there may be many possible orderings
for these updates. Now, the point is if imagine you’re an observer in this universe. So, and you
say, did something get updated? Well, you don’t in any sense know until you yourself have been
updated. Right. So in fact, all that you can be sensitive to is essentially the causal network
of how an event over there affects an event that’s in you. That doesn’t even feel like
observation. That’s like, that’s something else. You’re just part of the whole thing.
Yes, you’re part of it. But, but even to have, so the end result of that is all you’re sensitive to
is this causal network of what event affects what other event. I’m not making a big statement about
sort of the structure of the observer. I’m simply saying, I’m simply making the argument that
what happens, the microscopic order of these rewrites is not something that any observer,
any conceivable observer in this universe can be affected by. Because the only thing the observer
can be affected by is this causal network of how the events in the observer are affected
by other events that happen in the universe. So the only thing you have to look at is the
causal network. You don’t really have to look at this microscopic rewriting that’s happening. So
these rewrites are happening wherever they, they happen wherever they feel like.
Causal network. Is there, you said that there’s not really, so the idea would be an undefined,
like what gets updated? The, the sequence of things is undefined. It’s a, yes. That’s what
you mean by the causal network, but then the call, no, the causal network is given that an
update has happened. That’s an event. Then the question is, is that event causally related to,
does that event, if that event didn’t happen, then some future event couldn’t happen yet.
Gotcha.
And so you build up this network of what affects what. Okay. And so what that does,
so when you build up that network, that’s kind of the observable aspect of the universe in some
sense. And so then you can ask questions about, you know, how robust is that observable network
of the, what’s happening in the universe. Okay. So here’s where it starts getting kind of
interesting. So for certain kinds of microscopic rewriting rules, the order of rewrites does not
matter to the causal network. And so this is, okay, mathematical logic moment. This is equivalent
to the Church Rosser property or the confluence property of rewrite rules. And it’s the same
reason that if you’re simplifying an algebraic expression, for example, you can say, oh, let me
expand those terms out. Let me factor those pieces. Doesn’t matter what order you do that in,
you’ll always get the same answer. And that’s, it’s the same fundamental phenomenon that causes
for certain kinds of microscopic rewrite rules that causes the causal network to be independent
of the microscopic order of rewritings.
Why is that property important?
Because it implies special relativity. I mean, the reason it’s important is that that property,
special relativity says you can look at these sort of, you can look at different reference frames.
You can have different, you can be looking at your notion of what space and what’s time
can be different depending on whether you’re traveling at a certain speed, depending on
whether you’re doing this, that, and the other. But nevertheless, the laws of physics are the
same. That’s what the principle of special relativity says, is the laws of physics are
the same independent of your reference frame. Well, turns out this sort of change of the
microscopic rewriting order is essentially equivalent to a change of reference frame,
or at least there’s a sub part of how that works that’s equivalent to change a reference frame.
So, somewhat surprisingly, and sort of for the first time in forever,
it’s possible for an underlying microscopic theory to imply special relativity, to be able to derive
it. It’s not something you put in as a, this is a, it’s something where this other property,
causal invariance, which is also the property that implies that there’s a single thread of time
in the universe. It might not be the case that that’s what would lead to the possibility of an
observer thinking that definite stuff happens. Otherwise, you’ve got all these possible rewriting
orders, and who’s to say which one occurred. But with this causal invariance property,
there’s a notion of a definite thread of time. It sounds like that kind of idea of time,
even space, would be emergent from the system. Oh, yeah. No, I mean, it’s not a fundamental part
of the system. No, no, it’s a fundamental level. All you’ve got is a bunch of nodes connected by
hyper edges or whatever. So there’s no time, there’s no space. That’s right. And
but the thing is that it’s just like imagining, imagine you’re just dealing with a graph. And
imagine you have something like a, you know, like a honeycomb graph, or you have a hexagon,
a bunch of hexagons. You know, that graph at a microscopic level, it’s just a bunch of nodes
connected to other nodes. But at a macroscopic level, you say that looks like a honeycomb,
you know, lattice, it looks like a two dimensional, you know, manifold of some kind, it looks like a
two dimensional thing. If you connect it differently, if you just connect all the
nodes one, one to another, and kind of a sort of linked list type structure, then you’d say,
well, that looks like a one dimensional space. But at the microscopic level, all these are just
networks with nodes, the macroscopic level, they look like something that’s like one of our sort
of familiar kinds of space. And it’s the same thing with these hyper graphs. Now, if you ask me,
have I found one that gives me three dimensional space? The answer is not yet. So we don’t know.
This is one of these things we’re kind of betting against nature, so to speak. And I have no way to
know. And so there are many other properties of this kind of system that are very beautiful,
actually, and very suggestive. And it will be very elegant if this turns out to be right,
because it’s very clean. I mean, you start with nothing. And everything gets built up,
everything about space, everything about time, everything about matter. It’s all just emergent
from the properties of this extremely low level system. And that, that will be pretty cool if
that’s the way our universe works. Now, do I on the other hand, the thing that that I find very
confusing is, let’s say we succeed, let’s say we can say this particular sort of hypergraph rewriting
rule gives the universe just run that hypergraph rewriting rule for enough times, and you’ll get
everything, you’ll get this conversation we’re having, you’ll get everything. It’s that if we
get to that point, and we look at what is this thing, what is this rule that we just have,
that is giving us our whole universe, how do we think about that thing? Let’s say, turns out the
minimal version of this, and this is kind of cool thing for a language designer like me,
the minimal version of this model is actually a single line of orphan language code.
So that’s, which I wasn’t sure was going to happen that way, but it’s, it’s a, that’s, it’s kind of,
no, we don’t know what, we don’t know what that’s, that’s just the framework to know the actual
particular hypergraph that might be a longer, the specification of the rules might be slightly
longer. How does that help you accept marveling in the beauty and the elegance of the simplicity
that creates the universe? That does that help us predict anything in the universe?
That does that help us predict anything? Not really because of the irreducibility.
That’s correct. That’s correct. But so the thing that is really strange to me,
and I haven’t wrapped my, my brain around this yet is, you know, one is one keeps on realizing
that we’re not special in the sense that, you know, we don’t live at the center of the universe.
We don’t blah, blah, blah. And yet if we produce a rule for the universe and it’s quite simple,
and we can write it down and a couple of lines or something that feels very special.
How did we come to get a simple universe when many of the available universes, so to speak,
are incredibly complicated? It might be, you know, a quintillion characters long.
Why did we get one of the ones that’s simple? And so I haven’t wrapped my brain around that
issue yet. If indeed we are in such a simple, the universe is such a simple rule. Is it possible
that there is something outside of this that we are in a kind of what people call the simulation,
right? That we’re just part of a computation that’s being explored by a graduate student
in alternate universe. Well, you know, the problem is we don’t get to say much about
what’s outside our universe because by definition, our universe is what we exist within. Now,
can we make a sort of almost theological conclusion from being able to know how our
particular universe works? Interesting question. I don’t think that if you ask the question,
could we, and it relates again to this question about extraterrestrial intelligence, you know,
we’ve got the rule for the universe. Was it built in on purpose? Hard to say. That’s the same thing
as saying we see a signal from, you know, that we’re receiving from some random star somewhere,
and it’s a series of pulses. And, you know, it’s a periodic series of pulses, let’s say.
Was that done on purpose? Can we conclude something about the origin of that series of
pulses? Just because it’s elegant does not necessarily mean that somebody created it or
that we can even comprehend. Yeah. I think it’s the ultimate version of the sort of identification
of the techno signature question. It’s the ultimate version of that is was our universe
a piece of technology, so to speak, and how on earth would we know? But I mean, in the kind of
crazy science fiction thing you could imagine, you could say, oh, there’s going to be a signature
there. It’s going to be made by so and so. But there’s no way we could understand that,
so to speak, and it’s not clear what that would mean. Because the universe simply,
you know, if we find a rule for the universe, we’re simply saying that rule represents what
our universe does. We’re not saying that that rule is something running on a big computer
and making our universe. It’s just saying that represents what our universe does in the same
sense that, you know, laws of classical mechanics, differential equations, whatever they are,
represent what mechanical systems do. It’s not that the mechanical systems are somehow running
solutions to those differential equations. Those differential equations are just representing the
behavior of those systems. So what’s the gap in your sense to linger on the fascinating,
perhaps slightly sci fi question? What’s the gap between understanding the fundamental rules that
create a universe and engineering a system, actually creating a simulation ourselves?
So you’ve talked about sort of, you’ve talked about, you know, nano engineering kind of ideas
that are kind of exciting, actually creating some ideas of computation in the physical space. How
hard is it as an engineering problem to create the universe once you know the rules that create it?
Well, that’s an interesting question. I think the substrate on which the universe is operating is
not a substrate that we have access to. I mean, the only substrate we have is that same substrate
that the universe is operating in. So if the universe is a bunch of hypergraphs being rewritten,
then we get to attach ourselves to those same hypergraphs being rewritten. We don’t get to,
and if you ask the question, you know, is the code clean? You know, can we write nice,
elegant code with efficient algorithms and so on? Well, that’s an interesting question.
That’s this question of how much computational reducibility there is in the system.
But I’ve seen some beautiful cellular automata that basically create copies of itself within
itself, right? So that’s the question whether it’s possible to create, like whether you need
to understand the substrate or whether you can. Yeah, well, right. I mean, so one of the things
that is sort of one of my slightly sci fi thoughts about the future, so to speak, is, you know,
right now, if you poll typical people, you say, do you think it’s important to find the fundamental
theory of physics? You get, because I’ve done this poll informally, at least, it’s curious,
actually, you get a decent fraction of people saying, oh, yeah, that would be pretty interesting.
I think that’s becoming, surprisingly enough, more, I mean, a lot of people are interested
in physics in a way that like, without understanding it, just kind of watching
scientists, a very small number of them struggle to understand the nature of our reality.
Right. I mean, I think that’s somewhat true. And in fact, in this project that I’m launching into
to try and find fundamental theory of physics, I’m going to do it as a very public project. I mean,
it’s going to be live streamed and all this kind of stuff. And I don’t know what will happen. It’ll
be kind of fun. I mean, I think that it’s the interface to the world of this project. I mean,
I figure one feature of this project is, you know, unlike technology projects that basically are what
they are, this is a project that might simply fail, because it might be the case that it generates
all kinds of elegant mathematics that has absolutely nothing to do with the physical
universe that we happen to live in. Okay, so we’re talking about kind of the quest to find
the fundamental theory of physics. First point is, you know, it’s turned out it’s kind of hard
to find the fundamental theory of physics. People weren’t sure that that would be the case. Back in
the early days of applying mathematics to science, 1600s and so on, people were like, oh, in 100 years
we’ll know everything there is to know about how the universe works. Turned out to be harder than
that. And people got kind of humble at some level, because every time we got to sort of a greater
level of smallness and studying the universe, it seemed like the math got more complicated and
everything got harder. When I was a kid, basically, I started doing particle physics. And when I was
doing particle physics, I always thought finding the fundamental, fundamental theory of physics,
that’s a kooky business, we’ll never be able to do that. But we can operate within these
frameworks that we built for doing quantum field theory and general relativity and things like this.
And it’s all good. And we can figure out a lot of stuff. Did you even at that time have a sense
that there’s something behind that? Sure, I just didn’t expect that. I thought in some rather un,
it’s actually kind of crazy and thinking back on it, because it’s kind of like there was this long
period in civilization where people thought the ancients had it all figured out, and we’ll never
figure out anything new. And to some extent, that’s the way I felt about physics when I was
in the middle of doing it, so to speak, was, you know, we’ve got quantum field theory, it’s the
foundation of what we’re doing. And there’s, you know, yes, there’s probably something underneath
this, but we’ll sort of never figure it out. But then I started studying simple programs in the
computational universe, things like cellular automata and so on. And I discovered that
they do all kinds of things that were completely at odds with the intuition that I had had.
And so after that, after you see this tiny little program that does all this amazingly complicated
stuff, then you start feeling a bit more ambitious about physics and saying, maybe we could do this
for physics too. And so that got me started years ago now in this kind of idea of could we actually
find what’s underneath all of these frameworks, like quantum field theory and general relativity
and so on. And people perhaps don’t realize as clearly as they might that, you know, the
frameworks we’re using for physics, which is basically these two things, quantum field theory,
sort of the theory of small stuff and general relativity, theory of gravitation and large stuff.
Those are the two basic theories. And they’re 100 years old. I mean, general relativity was 1915,
quantum field theory, well, 1920s. So basically 100 years old. And it’s been a good run. There’s
a lot of stuff been figured out. But what’s interesting is the foundations haven’t changed
in all that period of time, even though the foundations had changed several times before
that in the 200 years earlier than that. And I think the kinds of things that I’m thinking about,
which are sort of really informed by thinking about computation and the computational universe,
it’s a different foundation. It’s a different set of foundations. And might be wrong. But it is at
least, you know, we have a shot. And I think it’s, you know, to me, it’s, you know, my personal
calculation for myself is, is, you know, if it turns out that the finding the fundamental theory
of physics, it’s kind of low hanging fruit, so to speak, it’d be a shame if we just didn’t think to
do it. You know, if people just said, Oh, you’ll never figure that stuff out. Let’s, you know,
and it takes another 200 years before anybody gets around to doing it. You know, I think it’s,
I don’t know how low hanging this fruit actually is. It may be, you know, it may be that it’s kind
of the wrong century to do this project. I mean, I think the cautionary tale for me, you know,
I think about things that I’ve tried to do in technology, where people thought about doing them
a lot earlier. And my favorite example is probably Leibniz, who, who thought about making essentially
encapsulating the world’s knowledge in a computational form in the late 1600s, and did a
lot of things towards that. And basically, you know, we finally managed to do this. But he was
300 years too early. And that’s the that’s kind of the in terms of life planning. It’s kind of like,
avoid things that can’t be done in your in your century, so to speak.
Yeah, timing. Timing is everything. So you think if we kind of figure out the underlying rules
that can create from which quantum field theory and general relativity can emerge,
do you think they’ll help us unify it at that level of abstraction?
Oh, we’ll know it completely. We’ll know how that all fits together. Yes, without a question.
And I mean, it’s already even the things I’ve already done. There are very, you know, it’s very,
very elegant, actually, how things seem to be fitting together. Now, you know, is it right?
I don’t know yet. It’s awfully suggestive. If it isn’t right, it’s then the designer of the universe
should feel embarrassed, so to speak, because it’s a really good way to do it.
And your intuition in terms of design universe, does God play dice? Is there is there randomness
in this thing? Or is it deterministic? So the kind of
That’s a little bit of a complicated question. Because when you’re dealing with these things
that involve these rewrites that have, okay, even randomness is an emergent phenomenon, perhaps.
Yes, yes. I mean, it’s a yeah, well, randomness, in many of these systems,
pseudo randomness and randomness are hard to distinguish. In this particular case,
the current idea that we have about some measurement in quantum mechanics
is something very bizarre and very abstract. And I don’t think I can yet
explain it without kind of yakking about very technical things. Eventually, I will be able to.
But if that’s right, it’s kind of a it’s a weird thing, because it slices between determinism and
randomness in a weird way that hasn’t been sliced before, so to speak. So like many of these
questions that come up in science, where it’s like, is it this or is it that? Turns out the
real answer is it’s neither of those things. It’s something kind of different and sort of orthogonal
to those categories. And so that’s the current, you know, this week’s idea about how that might
work. But, you know, we’ll see how that unfolds. I mean, there’s this question about a field like
physics and sort of the quest for fundamental theory and so on. And there’s both the science
of what happens and there’s the sort of the social aspect of what happens. Because, you know,
in a field that is basically as old as physics, we’re at, I don’t know what it is, fourth generation,
I don’t know, fifth generation, I don’t know what generation it is of physicists. And like,
I was one of these, so to speak. And for me, the foundations were like the pyramid, so to speak,
you know, it was that way. And it was always that way. It is difficult in an old field to go back to
the foundations and think about rewriting them. It’s a lot easier in young fields where you’re
still dealing with the first generation of people who invented the field. And it tends to be the
case, you know, that the nature of what happens in science tends to be, you know, you’ll get,
typically the pattern is some methodological advance occurs. And then there’s a period of five
years, 10 years, maybe a little bit longer than that, where there’s lots of things that are now
made possible by that methodological advance, whether it’s, you know, I don’t know, telescopes,
or whether that’s some mathematical method or something. Something happens, a tool gets built,
and then you can do a bunch of stuff. And there’s a bunch of low hanging fruit to be picked. And
that takes a certain amount of time. After all that low hanging fruit is picked, then it’s a hard
slog for the next however many decades or century or more to get to the next sort of level at which
one could do something. And it’s kind of a, and it tends to be the case that in fields that are in
that kind of, I wouldn’t say cruise mode, because it’s really hard work, but it’s very hard work for
very incremental progress. And then in your career and some of the things you’ve taken on,
it feels like you’re not, you haven’t been afraid of the hard slog. Yeah, that’s true. So it’s quite
interesting, especially on the engineering, on the engineering side. On a small tangent, when you
were at Caltech, did you get to interact with Richard Feynman at all? Do you have any memories
of Richard? We worked together quite a bit, actually. In fact, both when I was at Caltech
and after I left Caltech, we were both consultants at this company called Thinking Machines Corporation,
which was just down the street from here, actually. It was ultimately an ill fated company. But I used
to say this company is not going to work with the strategy they have. And Dick Feynman always used
to say, what do we know about running companies? Just let them run their company. But anyway,
he was not into that kind of thing. And he always thought that my interest in doing things like
running companies was a distraction, so to speak. And for me, it’s a mechanism to have a more
effective machine for actually getting things, figuring things out and getting things to happen.
Did he think of it, because essentially what you did with the company, I don’t know if you were
thinking of it that way, but you’re creating tools to empower the exploration of the
university. Do you think, did he… Did he understand that point? The point of tools of…
I think not as well as he might have done. I mean, I think that… But he was actually my
first company, which was also involved with, well, was involved with more mathematical computation
kinds of things. He was quite… He had lots of advice about the technical side of what we should
do and so on. Do you have examples, memories, or thoughts that… Oh, yeah, yeah. He had all
kinds of… Look, in the business of doing sort of… One of the hard things in math is doing
integrals and so on. And so he had his own elaborate ways to do integrals and so on. He
had his own ways of thinking about sort of getting intuition about how math works.
And so his sort of meta idea was take those intuitional methods and make a computer follow
those intuitional methods. Now, it turns out for the most part, like when we do integrals and
things, what we do is we build this kind of bizarre industrial machine that turns every integral
into products of major G functions and generates this very elaborate thing. And actually the big
problem is turning the results into something a human will understand. It’s not, quote,
doing the integral. And actually, Feynman did understand that to some extent. And I’m embarrassed
to say he once gave me this big pile of, you know, calculational methods for particle physics that he
worked out in the 50s. And he said, yeah, it’s more used to you than to me type thing. And I
was like, I’ve intended to look at it and give it back and I’m still on my files now. But that’s
what happens when it’s finiteness of human lives. Maybe if he’d live another 20 years, I would have
remembered to give it back. But I think that was his attempt to systematize the ways that one does
integrals that show up in particle physics and so on. Turns out the way we’ve actually done it
is very different from that way. What do you make of that difference,
Eugene? So Feynman was actually quite remarkable at creating sort of intuitive frameworks for
understanding difficult concepts. I’m smiling because, you know, the funny thing about him was
that the thing he was really, really, really good at is calculating stuff. But he thought that was
easy because he was really good at it. And so he would do these things where he would calculate
some, do some complicated calculation in quantum field theory, for example, come out with a result,
wouldn’t tell anybody about the complicated calculation because he thought that was easy.
He thought the really impressive thing was to have this simple intuition about how
everything works. So he invented that at the end. And, you know, because he’d done this calculation
and knew how it worked, it was a lot easier. It’s a lot easier to have good intuition when you know
what the answer is. And then and then he would just not tell anybody about these calculations
that he wasn’t meaning that maliciously, so to speak. It’s just he thought that was easy.
And and that’s, you know, that led to areas where people were just completely mystified,
and they kind of followed his intuition. But nobody could tell why it worked. Because actually,
the reason it worked was because he’d done all these calculations, and he knew that it was
would work. And, you know, when I he and I worked a bit on quantum computers actually back in 1980,
81, before anybody had heard of those things. And, you know, the typical mode of I mean,
he was used to say, and I now think about this, because I’m about the age that he was when I
worked with him. And, you know, I see the people who are one third my age, so to speak.
And he was always complaining that I was one third his age, and therefore various things. But, but,
you know, he would do some calculation by by hand, you know, blackboard and things come up with some
answer. I’d say, I don’t understand this. You know, I do something with a computer. And he’d say,
you know, I don’t understand this. So there’d be some big argument about what was, you know,
what was going on, but but it was always some. And I think, actually, we many of the things that we
sort of realized about quantum computing, that was sort of issues that have to do particularly
with the measurement process, are kind of still issues today. And I kind of find it interesting.
It’s a funny thing in science that these, you know, that there’s, there’s a remarkable happens
in technology to there’s a remarkable sort of repetition of history that ends up occurring.
Eventually, things really get nailed down. But it often takes a while. And it often things come
back decades later. Well, for example, I could tell a story actually happened right down the
street from here. When we were both thinking machines, I had been working on this particular
cellular automaton, who rule 30, that has this feature that it from very simple initial conditions,
it makes really complicated behavior. Okay. So and actually, of all silly physical things,
using this big parallel computer called the connection machine that that company was making,
I generated this giant printout of rule 30 on very, on actually on the same kind of same kind
of printer that people use to make layouts microprocessors. So one of these big, you know,
large format printers with high resolution and so on. So okay, so print this out lots of very tiny
cells. And so there was sort of a question of how some features of that pattern. And so it was very
much a physical, you know, on the floor with meter rules trying to measure different things.
So, so Feynman kind of takes me aside, we’ve been doing that for a little while and takes me aside.
And he says, I just want to know this one thing says, I want to know, how did you know that this
rule 30 thing would produce all this really complicated behavior that is so complicated
that we’re, you know, going around with this big printout, and so on. And I said, Well,
I didn’t know, I just enumerated all the possible rules and then observed that that’s what happened.
He said, Oh, I feel a lot better. You know, I thought you had some intuition that he didn’t have
that would let one. I said, No, no, no, no intuition, just experimental science.
TK Oh, that’s such a beautiful sort of dichotomy there of that’s exactly you showed is you really
can’t have an intuition about an irreducible. I mean, you have to run it.
MG Yes, that’s right.
TK That’s so hard for us humans, and especially brilliant
physicists like Feynman to say that you can’t have a compressed, clean intuition about how the whole
thing works. MG Yes, yes. No, he was, I mean, I think he was sort of on the edge of understanding
that point about computation. And I think he found that, I think he always found computation
interesting. And I think that was sort of what he was a little bit poking at. I mean, that intuition,
you know, the difficulty of discovering things, like even you say, Oh, you know, you just
enumerate all the cases and just find one that does something interesting, right? Sounds very easy.
Turns out, like, I missed it when I first saw it, because I had kind of an intuition
that said it shouldn’t be there. So I had kind of arguments, Oh, I’m going to ignore that case,
because whatever. And how did you have an open mind enough? Because you’re essentially the same
person as you should find, like the same kind of physics type of thinking. How did you find yourself
having a sufficiently open mind to be open to watching rules and them revealing complexity?
MG Yeah, I think that’s an interesting question. I’ve wondered about that myself, because it’s
kind of like, you know, you live through these things, and then you say, what was the historical
story? And sometimes the historical story that you realize after the fact was not what you lived
through, so to speak. And so, you know, what I realized is, I think what happened is, you know,
I did physics, kind of like reductionistic physics, where you’re thrown in the universe,
and you’re told, go figure out what’s going on inside it. And then I started building computer
tools. And I started building my first computer language, for example. And computer language is
not like, it’s sort of like physics in the sense that you have to take all those computations
people want to do, and kind of drill down and find the primitives that they can all be made of.
But then you do something that’s really different, because you’re just saying,
okay, these are the primitives. Now, you know, hopefully they’ll be useful to people,
let’s build up from there. So you’re essentially building an artificial universe, in a sense,
where you make this language, you’ve got these primitives, you’re just building whatever you
feel like building. And so it was sort of interesting for me, because from doing science,
where you’re just thrown in the universe as the universe is, to then just being told, you know,
you can make up any universe you want. And so I think that experience of making a computer language,
which is essentially building your own universe, so to speak, that’s what gave me a somewhat
different attitude towards what might be possible. It’s like, let’s just explore what can be done in
these artificial universes, rather than thinking the natural science way of let’s be constrained
by how the universe actually is. Yeah, by being able to program, essentially, you’ve,
as opposed to being limited to just your mind and a pen, you now have, you’ve basically built
another brain that you can use to explore the universe by computer program, you know,
this is kind of a brain, right? And it’s well, it’s it’s or telescope, or you know, it’s a tool,
it’s it lets you let’s you see stuff, but there’s something fundamentally different
between a computer and a telescope. I mean, it just, yeah, I’m hoping to romanticize the notion,
but it’s more general, the computer is more general. And it’s, it’s, I think, I mean, this
point about, you know, people say, oh, such and such a thing was almost discovered at such and
such a time, the the distance between, you know, the building the paradigm that allows you to
actually understand stuff or allows one to be open to seeing what’s going on. That’s really hard.
And, you know, I think, in I’ve been fortunate in my life that I spent a lot of my time building
computational language. And that’s an activity that, in a sense, works by sort of having to
kind of create another level of abstraction and kind of be open to different kinds of structures.
But, you know, it’s, it’s always I mean, I’m fully aware of, I suppose, the fact that I have seen it
a bunch of times of how easy it is to miss the obvious, so to speak, that at least is factored
into my attempt to not miss the obvious, although it may not succeed. What do you think is the role
of ego in the history of math and science? And more sort of, you know, a book title is something
like a new kind of science. You’ve accomplished a huge amount. In fact, somebody said that Newton
didn’t have an ego, and I looked into it and he had a huge ego. Yeah, but from an outsider’s
perspective, some have said that you have a bit of an ego as well. Do you see it that way? Does
ego get in the way? Is it empowering? Is it both? So it’s, it’s, it’s complicated and necessary. I
mean, you know, I’ve had, look, I’ve spent more than half my life CEO in a tech company. Right.
Okay. And, you know, that is a, I think it’s actually very, it means that one’s ego is not
a distant thing. It’s a thing that one encounters every day, so to speak, because it’s, it’s all
tied up with leadership and with how one, you know, develops an organization and all these
kinds of things. So, you know, it may be that if I’d been an academic, for example, I could have
sort of, you know, check the ego, put it on, put on a shelf somewhere and ignore its characteristics,
but you’re reminded of it quite often in the context of running a company. Sure. I mean,
that’s what it’s about. It’s, it’s about leadership and, you know, leadership is intimately tied to
ego. Now, what does it mean? I mean, what, what is the, you know, for me, I’ve been fortunate that I
think I have reasonable intellectual confidence, so to speak. That is, you know, I, I’m one of
these people who at this point, if somebody tells me something and I just don’t understand it,
my conclusion isn’t that means I’m dumb. That my conclusion is there’s something wrong with
what I’m being told. And that was actually Dick Feynman used to have that, that that feature too,
he never really believed in. He actually believed in experts much less than I believe in experts.
So. Wow. So that’s a fun, that’s a, that’s a fundamentally powerful property of ego and saying,
like, not that I am wrong, but that the, the world is wrong. And, and tell me, like, when confronted
with the fact that doesn’t fit the thing that you’ve really thought through sort of both the
negative and the positive of ego, do you see the negative of that get in the way sort of being
sure of the mistakes I’ve made that are the results of, I’m pretty sure I’m right. And
turns out I’m not. I mean, that’s, that’s the, you know, but, but the thing is that the, the,
the idea that one tries to do things that, so for example, you know, one question is if people have
tried hard to do something and then one thinks, maybe I should try doing this myself. Uh, if one
does not have a certain degree of intellectual confidence, one just says, well, people have been
trying to do this for a hundred years. How am I going to be able to do this? Yeah. And, you know,
I was fortunate in the sense that I happened to start having some degree of success in science
and things when I was really young. And so that developed a certain amount of sort of intellectual
confidence. I don’t think I otherwise would have had. Um, and you know, in a sense, I mean,
I was fortunate that I was working in a field, particle physics during its sort of golden age
of rapid progress. And that, that’s kind of gives one a false sense of, uh, achievement because
it’s kind of, kind of easy to discover stuff that’s going to survive. If you happen to be,
you know, picking the low hanging fruit of a rapidly expanding field.
I mean, the reason I totally, I totally immediately understood the ego behind a new
kind of science to me, let me sort of just try to express my feelings on the whole thing,
is that if you don’t allow that kind of ego, then you would never write that book.
That you would say, well, people must have done this. There’s not, you would not dig.
You would not keep digging. And I think that was, I think you have to take that ego and,
and ride it and see where it takes you. And that’s how you create exceptional work.
But I think the other point about that book was it was a non trivial question,
how to take a bunch of ideas that are, I think, reasonably big ideas. They might,
they might, you know, their importance is determined by what happens historically.
One can’t tell how important they are. One can tell sort of the scope of them.
And the scope is fairly big and they’re very different from things that have come before.
And the question is, how do you explain that stuff to people? And so I had had the experience
of sort of saying, well, there are these things, there’s a cellular automaton. It does this,
it does that. And people are like, oh, it must be just like this. It must be just like that.
So no, it isn’t. It’s something different. Right. And so I could have done sort of,
I’m really glad you did what you did, but you could have done sort of academically,
just published, keep publishing small papers here and there. And then you would just keep
getting this kind of resistance, right? You would get like, yeah, it’s supposed to just
dropping a thing that says, here it is, here’s the full, the full thing.
No, I mean, that was my calculation is that basically, you know, you could introduce
little pieces. It’s like, you know, one possibility is like, it’s the secret weapon,
so to speak. It’s this, you know, I keep on discovering these things in all these different
areas. Where’d they come from? Nobody knows. But I decided that, you know, in the interests of one
only has one life to lead and, you know, writing that book took me a decade anyway. There’s not a
lot of wiggle room, so to speak. One can’t be wrong by a factor of three, so to speak, in how long
it’s going to take. That I, you know, I thought the best thing to do, the thing that is most sort
of, that most respects the intellectual content, so to speak, is you just put it out with as much
force as you can, because it’s not something where, and, you know, it’s an interesting thing.
You talk about ego and it’s, you know, for example, I run a company which has my name on it,
right? I thought about starting a club for people whose companies have their names on them. And
it’s a funny group because we’re not a bunch of egomaniacs. That’s not what it’s about,
so to speak. It’s about basically sort of taking responsibility for what one’s doing.
And, you know, in a sense, any of these things where you’re sort of putting yourself on the line,
it’s kind of a funny, it’s a funny dynamic because, in a sense, my company is sort of
something that happens to have my name on it, but it’s kind of bigger than me and I’m kind of just
its mascot at some level. I mean, I also happen to be a pretty, you know, strong leader of it.
LW. But it’s basically showing a deep, inextricable sort of investment. Your name,
like Steve Jobs’s name wasn’t on Apple, but he was Apple. Elon Musk’s name is not on Tesla,
but he is Tesla. So it’s like, it meaning emotionally. If a company succeeds or fails,
he would just that emotionally would suffer through that. And so that’s, that’s a beautiful
recognizing that fact. And also Wolfram is a pretty good branding name, so that works out.
LW. Yeah, right. Exactly. I think Steve had it had a bad deal there.
LR. Yeah. So you made up for it with the last name. Okay. So in 2002, you published
A New Kind of Science, to which sort of on a personal level, I can credit my love for
cellular automata and computation in general. I think a lot of others can as well. Can you
briefly describe the vision, the hope, the main idea presented in this 1200 page book?
LW. Sure. Although it took 1200 pages to say in the book. So no, the real idea, it’s kind of
a good way to get into it is to look at sort of the arc of history and to look at what’s happened
in kind of the development of science. I mean, there was this sort of big idea in science about
300 years ago, that was, let’s use mathematical equations to try and describe things in the world.
Let’s use sort of the formal idea of mathematical equations to describe what might be happening in
the world, rather than, for example, just using sort of logical augmentation and so on. Let’s have
a formal theory about that. And so there’d been this 300 year run of using mathematical equations
to describe the natural world, which had worked pretty well. But I got interested in how one could
generalize that notion. There is a formal theory, there are definite rules, but what structure could
those rules have? And so what I got interested in was let’s generalize beyond the sort of purely
mathematical rules. And we now have this sort of notion of programming and computing and so on.
Let’s use the kinds of rules that can be embodied in programs as a sort of generalization of the
ones that can exist in mathematics as a way to describe the world. And so my kind of favorite
version of these kinds of simple rules are these things called cellular automata. And so typical
case… So wait, what are cellular automata? Fair enough. So typical case of a cellular automaton,
it’s an array of cells. It’s just a line of discrete cells. Each cell is either black or white.
And in a series of steps that you can represent as lines going down a page, you’re updating the
color of each cell according to a rule that depends on the color of the cell above it and
to its left and right. So it’s really simple. So a thing might be if the cell and its right neighbor
are not the same or the cell on the left is black or something, then make it black on the next step.
And if not, make it white. Typical rule. That rule, I’m not sure I said it exactly right,
but a rule very much like what I just said, has the feature that if you started off from just one
black cell at the top, it makes this extremely complicated pattern. So some rules you get a very
simple pattern. Some rules, the rule is simple. You start them off from a sort of simple seed.
You just get this very simple pattern. But other rules, and this was the big surprise when I
started actually just doing the simple computer experiments to find out what happens, is that they
produce very complicated patterns of behavior. So for example, this rule 30 rule has the feature
you start off from just one black cell at the top, makes this very random pattern. If you look
like at the center column of cells, you get a series of values. It goes black, white, black,
black, whatever it is. That sequence seems for all practical purposes random. So it’s kind of like
in math, you compute the digits of pi, 3.1415926, whatever. Those digits once computed, I mean,
the scheme for computing pi, it’s the ratio of the circumference to the diameter of a circle,
very well defined. But yet, once you’ve generated those digits, they seem for all practical
purposes completely random. And so it is with rule 30, that even though the rule is very simple,
much simpler, much more sort of computationally obvious than the rule for generating digits of pi,
even with a rule that simple, you’re still generating immensely complicated behavior.
Yeah. So if we could just pause on that, I think you probably have said it and looked at it so long,
you forgot the magic of it, or perhaps you don’t, you still feel the magic. But to me,
if you’ve never seen sort of, I would say, what is it? A one dimensional, essentially,
cellular automata, right? And you were to guess what you would see if you have some
sort of cells that only respond to its neighbors. Right. If you were to guess what kind of things
you would see, like my initial guess, like even when I first like opened your book,
A New Kind of Science, right? My initial guess is you would see, I mean, it would be a very simple
stuff. Right. And I think it’s a magical experience to realize the kind of complexity,
you mentioned rule 30, still your favorite cellular automaton? Still my favorite rule. Yes.
You get complexity, immense complexity, you get arbitrary complexity. Yes. And when you say
randomness down the middle column, that’s just one cool way to say that there’s incredible complexity.
And that’s just, I mean, that’s a magical idea. However, you start to interpret it,
all the reducibility discussions, all that. But it’s just, I think that has profound philosophical
kind of notions around it, too. It’s not just, I mean, it’s transformational about how you see the
world. I think for me it was transformational. I don’t know, we can have all kinds of discussion
about computation and so on, but just, you know, I sometimes think if I were on a desert island
and was, I don’t know, maybe it was some psychedelics or something, but if I had to take
one book, I mean, you kind of science would be it because you could just enjoy that notion. For some
reason, it’s a deeply profound notion, at least to me. I find it that way. Yeah. I mean, look, it’s
been, it was a very intuition breaking thing to discover. I mean, it’s kind of like, you know,
you point the computational telescope out the window and you’re like, okay, I’m going to
point the computational telescope out there. And suddenly you see, I don’t know, you know,
in the past, it’s kind of like, you know, moons of Jupiter or something, but suddenly you see
something that’s kind of very unexpected and rule 30 was very unexpected for me. And the big
challenge at a personal level was to not ignore it. I mean, people, you know, in other words,
you might say, you know, it’s a bug. What would you say? Yeah. Well, yeah. I mean, I,
what are we looking at by the way? Oh, well, I was just generating here. I’ll actually generate
a rule 30 pattern. So that’s the rule for, for rule 30. And it says, for example, it says here,
if you have a black cell in the middle and black cell to the left and white cell to the right,
then the cell on the next step will be white. And so here’s the actual pattern that you get
starting off from a single black cell at the top there. And then that’s the initial state initial
condition. That’s the initial thing. You just start off from that and then you’re going down
the page and at every, at every step, you’re just applying this rule to find out the new value that
you get. And so you might think rule that simple, you got to get the, there’s got to be some trace
of that simplicity here. Okay. We’ll run it. Let’s say for 400 steps. Um, so what it does,
it’s kind of aliasing a bit on the screen there, but, but, um, you can see there’s a little bit
of regularity over on the left, but there’s a lot of stuff here that just looks very complicated,
very random. And, uh, that’s a big sort of shock to was a big shock to my intuition, at least
that that’s possible. The mind immediately starts. Is there a pattern? There must be a repetitive
pattern. There must be. So I spent, so indeed, that’s what I thought at first. And I thought,
I thought, well, this is kind of interesting, but you know, if we run it long enough, we’ll see,
you know, something we’ll resolve into something simple. And, uh, uh, you know, I did all kinds of
analysis of using mathematics, statistics, cryptography, whatever, whatever to try and crack
it. Um, and I never succeeded. And after I hadn’t succeeded for a while, I started thinking maybe
there’s a real phenomenon here. That is the reason I’m not succeeding. Maybe. I mean, the thing that
for me was sort of a motivating factor was looking at the natural world and seeing all this complexity
that exists in the natural world. The question is, where does it come from? You know, what secret
does nature have that lets it make all this complexity that we humans, when we engineer
things typically are not making, we’re typically making things that at least look quite simple to
us. And so the shock here was even from something very simple, you’re making something that complex.
Uh, maybe this is getting at sort of the secret that nature has that allows it to make really
complex things, even though its underlying rules may not be that complex. How did it make you feel
if we, if we look at the Newton apple, was there, was it, was there a, you know, you took a walk
and, and something it profoundly hit you or was this a gradual thing, a lobster being boiled?
The truth of every sort of science discovery is it’s not that gradual. I mean, I’ve spent,
I happen to be interested in scientific biography kinds of things. And so I’ve tried to track down,
you know, how did people come to figure out this or that thing? And there’s always a long kind of,
uh, sort of preparatory, um, you know, there’s a, there’s a need to be prepared in a mindset
in which it’s possible to see something. I mean, in the case of rule 30,
I was around June 1st, 1984 was, um, uh, kind of a silly story in some ways. I finally had
a high resolution laser printer. So I was able, so I thought I’m going to generate a bunch of
pictures of the cellular automata and I generate this one and I put it, I was on some plane flight
to Europe and they have this with me. And it’s like, you know, I really should try to understand
this. And this is really, you know, this is, I really don’t understand what’s going on.
And, uh, that was kind of the, um, you know, slowly trying to, trying to see what was happening.
It was not, uh, it was depressingly unsubstantial, so to speak, in the sense that, um, a lot of these
ideas like principle of computational equivalence, for example, you know, I thought, well, that’s a
possible thing. I didn’t know if it’s correct, still don’t know for sure that it’s correct.
Um, but it’s sort of a gradual thing that these things gradually kind of become seem more important
than one thought. I mean, I think the whole idea of studying the computational universe of simple
programs, it took me probably a decade, decade and a half to kind of internalize that that was
really an important idea. Um, and I think, you know, if it turns out we find the whole universe
lurking out there in the computational universe, that’s a good, uh, you know, it’s a good brownie
point or something for the, uh, for the whole idea. But I think that the, um, the thing that’s
strange in this whole question about, you know, finding this different raw material for making
models of things, um, what’s been interesting sort of in the, in sort of arc of history is,
you know, for 300 years, it’s kind of like the, the mathematical equations approach.
It was the winner. It was the thing, you know, you want to have a really good model for something
that’s what you use. The thing that’s been remarkable is just in the last decade or so,
I think one can see a transition to using not mathematical equations, but programs
as sort of the raw material for making models of stuff. And that’s pretty neat. And it’s kind of,
you know, as somebody who’s kind of lived inside this paradigm shift, so to speak,
it is bizarre. I mean, no doubt in sort of the history of science that will be seen as an
instantaneous paradigm shift, but it sure isn’t instantaneous when it’s played out in one’s actual
life. So to speak, it seems glacial. Um, um, and it’s the kind of thing where, where it’s sort of
interesting because in the dynamics of sort of the adoption of ideas like that into different fields,
the younger the field, the faster the adoption typically, because people are not kind of locked
in with the fifth generation of people who’ve studied this field and it is, it is the way it is
and it can never be any different. And I think that’s been, um, you know, watching that process
has been interesting. I mean, I’m, I’m, I think I’m fortunate that I, I’ve, uh, uh, I, I do stuff
mainly cause I like doing it. And, um, uh, if I was, um, uh, that makes me kind of thick skinned
about the world’s response to what I do. Um, and uh, but that’s definitely, uh, you know, and anytime
you, you write a book called something like a new kind of science, um, it’s kind of the, the pitch
forks will come out for the, for the old kind of science. And I was, it was interesting dynamics.
I think that the, um, um, uh, I have to say that I was fully aware of the fact that the, um, when
you see sort of incipient paradigm shifts in science, the vigor of the negative response
upon early introduction is a fantastic positive indicator of good longterm results. So in other
words, if people just don’t care, it’s, um, you know, that’s not such a good sign. If they’re
like, oh, this is great. That means you didn’t really discover anything interesting. Um, what
fascinating properties of rule 30 have you discovered over the years? You’ve recently
announced the rule 30 prizes for solving three key problems. Can you maybe talk about interesting
properties that have been kind of revealed rule 30 or other cellular automata and what problems
are still before us? Like the three problems you’ve announced. Yeah. Yeah. Right. So, I mean,
the most interesting thing about cellular automata is that it’s hard to figure stuff out about them.
And that’s, um, uh, in a sense, every time you try and sort of, uh, uh, you try and bash them with
some other technique, you say, can I crack them? The answer is they seem to be uncrackable. They
seem to have the feature that they are, um, that they’re sort of showing irreducible computation.
They’re not, you’re not able to say, oh, I know exactly what this is going to do. It’s going to
do this or that, but there’s specific formulations of that fact. Yes. Right. So, I mean, for example,
in, in rule 30, in the pattern you get just starting from a single black cell, you get this
sort of very, very sort of random looking pattern. And so one feature of that, just look at the
center column. And for example, we use that for a long time to generate randomness symbols and
language, um, just, you know, what rule 30 produces. Now the question is, can you prove
how random it is? So for example, one very simple question, can you prove that it’ll never repeat?
We haven’t been able to show that it will never repeat.
We know that if there are two adjacent columns, we know they can’t both repeat,
but just knowing whether that center column can ever repeat, we still don’t even know that. Um,
another problem that I sort of put in my collection of, you know, it’s like $30,000 for
three, you know, for these three prizes for about rule 30. Um, I would say that this is not one of
those. There’s one of those cases where the money is not the main point, but, um, it’s just, uh,
you know, helps, um, uh, motivate somehow the, the investigation. So there’s three problems
you propose to get $30,000 if you solve all three or maybe, you know, it’s 10,000 for each for each.
Right. My, uh, the, the problems, that’s right. Money’s not the thing. The problems
themselves are just clean formulation. It’s just, you know, will it ever become periodic?
Second problem is, are there an equal number of black and white cells down the middle column,
down the middle column. And the third problem is a little bit harder to state, which is essentially,
is there a way of figuring out what the color of a cell at position T down the center column is
in a, with a less computational effort than about T steps. So in other words, is there a way to jump
ahead and say, I know what this is going to do, you know, it’s just some mathematical function
of T, um, or proving that there is no way or proving there is no way. Yes. But both, I mean,
you know, for any one of these, one could prove that, you know, one could discover, you know,
we know what rule 30 does for a billion steps, but, um, and maybe we’ll know for a trillion steps
before too very long. Um, but maybe at a quadrillion steps, it suddenly becomes repetitive.
You might say, how could that possibly happen? But so when I was writing up these prizes,
I thought, and this is typical of what happens in the computational universe. I thought,
let me find an example where it looks like it’s just going to be random forever,
but actually it becomes repetitive. And I found one and it’s just, you know, I did a search,
I searched, I don’t know, maybe a million different rules with some criterion. And this is
what’s sort of interesting about that is I kind of have this thing that I say in a kind of silly
way about the computational universe, which is, you know, the animals are always smarter than you
are. That is, there’s always some way. One of these computational systems is going to figure
out how to do something, even though I can’t imagine how it’s going to do it. And, you know,
I didn’t think I would find one that, you know, you would think after all these years that when
I found sort of all possible things, uh, uh, uh, funky things that, um, uh, that I would have, uh,
that I would have gotten my intuition wrapped around the idea that, um, you know, these creatures
are always in the computational universe are always smarter than I’m going to be. But, uh,
well, they’re equivalently as smart, right? That’s correct. And that makes it,
that makes one feel very sort of, it’s, it’s, it’s humbling every time because every time the thing
is, is, uh, you know, you think it’s going to do this or it’s not going to be possible to do this
and it turns out it finds a way. Of course, the promising thing is there’s a lot of other rules
like rule 30. It’s just rule 30 is, oh, it’s my favorite cause I found it first. And that’s right.
But the, the problems are focusing on rule 30. It’s possible that rule 30
is, is repetitive after trillion steps and that doesn’t prove anything about the other rules.
It does not. But this is a good sort of experiment of how you go about trying to prove something
about a particular rule. Yes. And it also, all these things help build intuition. That is if
it turned out that this was repetitive after a trillion steps, that’s not what I would expect.
And so we learned something from that. The method to do that though, would reveal something
interesting about the, no doubt. No doubt. I mean, it’s, although it’s sometimes challenging,
like the, you know, I put out a prize in 2007 for, for a particular Turing machine that I,
there was the simplest candidate for being a universal Turing machine and the young chap in
England named Alex Smith, um, after a smallish number of months said, I’ve got a proof and
he did, you know, it took a little while to iterate, but he had a proof. Unfortunately,
the proof is very, it’s, it’s a lot of micro details. It’s, it’s not, it’s not like you look
at it and you say, aha, there’s a big new principle. The big new principle is the simplest
Turing machine that might have been universal actually is universal. And it’s incredibly much
simpler than the Turing machines that people already knew were universal before that. And so
that intuitionally is important because it says computation universality is closer at hand than
you might’ve thought. Um, but the actual methods are not, uh, in that particular case,
we’re not terribly illuminating. It would be nice if the methods would also be elegant.
That’s true. Yeah. No, I mean, I think it’s, it’s one of these things where, I mean, it’s,
it’s like a lot of, we’ve talked about earlier kind of, um, you know, opening up AI’s and machine
learning and things of what’s going on inside and is it, is it just step by step or can you
sort of see the bigger picture more abstractly? It’s unfortunate. I mean, with Fermat’s last
theorem proof, it’s unfortunate that the proof to such an elegant theorem is, um, is not, I mean,
it’s, it’s, it’s not, it doesn’t fit into the margins of a page. That’s true. But there’s no,
one of the things is that’s another consequence of computational irreducibility. This, this fact
that there are even quite short results in mathematics whose proofs are arbitrarily long.
Yes. That’s a, that’s a consequence of all this stuff. And it’s, it’s a, it makes one wonder,
uh, you know, how come mathematics is possible at all? Right. Why is, you know, why is it the
case? How people managed to navigate doing mathematics through looking at things where
they’re not just thrown into, it’s all undecidable. Um, that’s, that’s its own own separate, separate
story. And that would be, that would, that would have a poetic beauty to it is if people were to
find something interesting about rule 30, because I mean, there’s an emphasis to this particular
role. It wouldn’t say anything about the broad irreducibility of all computations, but it would
nevertheless put a few smiles on people’s faces of, uh, well, yeah. But to me, it’s like in a
sense, establishing principle of computational equivalence, it’s a little bit like doing
inductive science anywhere. That is the more examples you find, the more convinced you are
that it’s generally true. I mean, we don’t get to, you know, whenever we do natural science,
we, we say, well, it’s true here that this or that happens. Can we, can we prove that it’s true
everywhere in the universe? No, we can’t. So, you know, it’s the same thing here. We’re exploring
the computational universe. We’re establishing facts in the computational universe. And that’s,
uh, that’s sort of a way of, uh, of inductively concluding general things. Just to think through
this a little bit, we’ve touched on it a little bit before, but what’s the difference between the
kind of computation, now that we’re talking about cellular automata, what’s the difference between
the kind of computation, biological systems, our mind, our bodies, the things we see before us that
emerged through the process of evolution and cellular automata? I mean, we’ve kind of implied
to the discussion of physics underlying everything, but we, we talked about the potential equivalents
of the fundamental laws of physics and the kind of computation going on in Turing machines.
But can you now connect that? Do you think there’s something special or interesting about the kind
of computation that our bodies do? Right. Well, let’s talk about brains primarily. I mean,
I think the, um, the most important thing about the things that our brains do are that we care
about them in the sense that there’s a lot of computation going on out there in, you know,
cellular automata and, and, you know, physical systems and so on. And it just, it does what it
does. It follows those rules. It does what it does. The thing that’s special about the computation in
our brains is that it’s connected to our goals and our kind of whole societal story. And, you know,
I think that’s the, that’s, that’s the special feature. And now the question then is when you
see this whole sort of ocean of computation out there, how do you connect that to the things that
we humans care about? And in a sense, a large part of my life has been involved in sort of the
technology of how to do that. And, you know, what I’ve been interested in is kind of building
computational language that allows that something that both we humans can understand and that can
be used to determine computations that are actually computations we care about. See, I think
when you look at something like one of these cellular automata and it does some complicated
thing, you say, that’s fun, but why do I care? Well, you could say the same thing actually in
physics. You say, oh, I’ve got this material and it’s a ferrite or something. Why do I care? You
know, it’s some, has some magnetic properties. Why do I care? It’s amusing, but why do I care?
Well, we end up caring because, you know, ferrite is what’s used to make magnetic tape,
magnetic discs, whatever. Or, you know, we could use liquid crystals as made, used to make,
well, not actually increasingly not, but it has been used to make computer displays and so on.
But those are, so in a sense, we’re mining these things that happen to exist in the physical
universe and making it be something that we care about because we sort of entrain it into
technology. And it’s the same thing in the computational universe that a lot of what’s
out there is stuff that’s just happening, but sometimes we have some objective and we will
go and sort of mine the computational universe for something that’s useful for some particular
objective. On a large scale, trying to do that, trying to sort of navigate the computational
universe to do useful things, you know, that’s where computational language comes in. And, you
know, a lot of what I’ve spent time doing and building this thing we call Wolfram Language,
which I’ve been building for the last one third of a century now. And kind of the goal there is
to have a way to express kind of computational thinking, computational thoughts in a way that
both humans and machines can understand. So it’s kind of like in the tradition of computer languages,
programming languages, that the tradition there has been more, let’s take how computers are built
and let’s specify, let’s have a human way to specify, do this, do this, do this,
at the level of the way that computers are built. What I’ve been interested in is representing sort
of the whole world computationally and being able to talk about whether it’s about cities or
chemicals or, you know, this kind of algorithm or that kind of algorithm, things that have come to
exist in our civilization and the sort of knowledge base of our civilization, being able to talk
directly about those in a computational language so that both we can understand it and computers
can understand it. I mean, the thing that I’ve been sort of excited about recently, which I had
only realized recently, which is kind of embarrassing, but it’s kind of the arc of what
we’ve tried to do in building this kind of computational language is it’s a similar kind of
arc of what happened when mathematical notation was invented. So go back 400 years, people were
trying to do math, they were always explaining their math in words, and it was pretty clunky.
And as soon as mathematical notation was invented, you could start defining things like algebra and
later calculus and so on. It all became much more streamlined. When we deal with computational
thinking about the world, there’s a question of what is the notation? What is the kind of
formalism that we can use to talk about the world computationally? In a sense, that’s what I’ve
spent the last third of a century trying to build. And we finally got to the point where
we have a pretty full scale computational language that sort of talks about the world.
And that’s exciting because it means that just like having this mathematical notation, let us
talk about the world mathematically, and let us build up these kind of mathematical sciences.
Now we have a computational language which allows us to start talking about the world
computationally, and lets us, my view of it is it’s kind of computational X for all X. All these
different fields of computational this, computational that. That’s what we can now build.
Let’s step back. So first of all, the mundane. What is Wolfram language in terms of,
I mean I can answer the question for you, but it’s basically not the philosophical deep,
the profound, the impact of it. I’m talking about in terms of tools, in terms of things you can
download, in terms of stuff you can play with. What is it? What does it fit into the infrastructure?
What are the different ways to interact with it?
Right. So I mean the two big things that people have sort of perhaps heard of that come from
Wolfram language, one is Mathematica, the other is Wolfram Alpha. So Mathematica first came out
in 1988. It’s this system that is basically an instance of Wolfram language, and it’s used to do
computations, particularly in sort of technical areas. And the typical thing you’re doing is
you’re typing little pieces of computational language, and you’re getting computations done.
It’s very kind of, there’s like a symbolic.
Yeah, it’s a symbolic language.
It’s a symbolic language. I mean I don’t know how to cleanly express that, but that makes it very
distinct from how we think about sort of, I don’t know, programming in a language like Python or
something.
Right. So the point is that in a traditional programming language, the raw material of the
programming language is just stuff that computers intrinsically do. And the point of Wolfram
language is that what the language is talking about is things that exist in the world or things
that we can imagine and construct. It’s aimed to be an abstract language from the beginning.
And so for example, one feature it has is that it’s a symbolic language, which means that the
thing called, you have an X, just type in X, and Wolfram language will just say, oh, that’s X.
It won’t say error, undefined thing. I don’t know what it is, computation, in terms of computing.
Now that X could perfectly well be the city of Boston. That’s a thing. That’s a symbolic thing.
Or it could perfectly well be the trajectory of some spacecraft represented as a symbolic thing.
And that idea that one can work with, sort of computationally work with these different,
these kinds of things that exist in the world or describe the world, that’s really powerful.
And when I started designing, well, when I designed the predecessor of what’s now Wolfram
language, which is a thing called SMP, which was my first computer language, I kind of wanted to
have this sort of infrastructure for computation, which was as fundamental as possible. I mean,
this is what I got for having been a physicist and tried to find fundamental components of things
and wound up with this kind of idea of transformation rules for symbolic expressions
as being sort of the underlying stuff from which computation would be built.
And that’s what we’ve been building from in Wolfram language. And operationally, what happens,
it’s, I would say, by far the highest level computer language that exists. And it’s really
been built in a very different direction from other languages. So other languages have been
about, there is a core language. It really is kind of wrapped around the operations that a
computer intrinsically does. Maybe people add libraries for this or that, but the goal of
Wolfram language is to have the language itself be able to cover this sort of very broad range
of things that show up in the world. And that means that there are 6,000 primitive functions
in the Wolfram language that cover things. I could probably pick a random here. I’m going to pick
just for fun, I’ll pick, let’s take a random sample of all the things that we have here.
So let’s just say random sample of 10 of them and let’s see what we get.
Wow. Okay. So these are really different things from functions. These are all functions,
Boolean convert. Okay. That’s the thing for converting between different types of Boolean
expressions. So for people are just listening, uh, Stephen typed in random sample of names,
so this is sampling from all function. How many you said there might be 6,000 from 6,000 10 of
them. And there’s a hilarious variety of them. Yeah, right. Well, we’ve got things about, um,
dollar requester address that has to do with interacting with, uh, uh, the, the world of the,
of the cloud and so on. Discrete wavelet data, spheroidal, graphical sort of window. Yeah. Yeah.
Window movable. That’s the user interface kind of thing. I want to pick another 10 cause I think
this is some, okay. So yeah, there’s a lot of infrastructure stuff here that you see. If you,
if you just start sampling at random, there’s a lot of kind of infrastructural things. If you’re
more, you know, if you more look at the, um, some of the exciting machine learning stuff you showed
off, is that also in this pool? Oh yeah. Yeah. I mean, you know, so one of those functions is
like image identify as a, as a function here where you just say image identify. I don’t know. It’s
always good to, let’s do this. Let’s say current image and let’s pick up an image, hopefully.
Current image accessing the webcam, took a picture yourself.
Took a terrible picture. But anyway, we can say image identify, open square brackets, and then
we just paste that picture in there. Image identify function running on the picture.
Oh, and it says, Oh wow. It says I, it looked, I looked like a plunger because I got this great
big thing behind my classifies. So this image identify classifies the most likely object in,
in the image. So, so plunger. Okay. That’s, that’s a bit embarrassing. Let’s see what it does.
And let’s pick the top 10. Um, okay. Well, it thinks there’s a, Oh, it thinks it’s pretty
unlikely that it’s a primate, a hominid, a person. 8% probability. 57 is a plunger.
Yeah. Well, hopefully we’ll not give you an existential crisis. And then, uh,
8%, uh, I shouldn’t say percent, but, uh, no, that’s right. 8% that it’s a hominid. Um, and,
uh, yeah. Okay. It’s really, I’m going to do another one of these just cause I’m embarrassed
that it, um, I didn’t see me at all. There we go. Let’s try that. Let’s see what that did.
Um, we took a picture with a little bit more of me and not just my bald head, so to speak.
Okay. 89% probability it’s a person. So that, so then I would, um, but, uh, you know, so this is
image identify as an example of one of just one of them, just one function out of that part of the
that’s like part of the language. Yes. And I mean, you know, something like, um, I could say,
I don’t know, let’s find the geo nearest, uh, what could we find? Um, let’s find the nearest volcano.
Um, let’s find the 10. I wonder where it thinks here is. Let’s try finding the 10 volcanoes
nearest here. Okay. So geo nearest volcano here, 10 nearest volcanoes. Right. Let’s find out where
those are. We can now, we’ve got a list of volcanoes out and I can say geo list plot that
and hopefully, okay, so there we go. So there’s a map that shows the positions of those 10 volcanoes
of the East coast and the Midwest and well, no, we’re okay. We’re okay. There’s not, it’s not too
bad. Yeah. They’re not very close to us. We could, we could measure how far away they are, but, um,
you know, the fact that right in the language, it knows about all the volcanoes in the world. It
knows, you know, computing what the nearest ones are. It knows all the maps of the world and so on.
It’s a fundamentally different idea of what a language is. Yeah, right. That’s why I like to
talk about is that, you know, a full scale computational language. That’s, that’s what
we’ve tried to do. And just if you can comment briefly, I mean, this kind of,
the Wolfram language along with Wolfram Alpha represents kind of what the dream of what AI is
supposed to be. There’s now a sort of a craze of learning kind of idea that we can take raw data
and from that extract the, uh, the different hierarchies of abstractions in order to be able
to under, like in order to form the kind of things that Wolfram language operates with,
but we’re very far from learning systems being able to form that.
Like the context of history of AI, if you could just comment on, there is a, you said computation
X and there’s just some sense where in the eighties and nineties sort of expert systems
represented a very particular computation X. Yes. Right. And there’s a kind of notion that
those efforts didn’t pan out. Right. But then out of that emerges kind of Wolfram language,
Wolfram Alpha, which is the success. I mean, yeah, right. I think those are in some sense,
those efforts were too modest. That is they were, they were looking at particular areas
and you actually can’t do it with a particular area. I mean, like, like even a problem like
natural language understanding, it’s critical to have broad knowledge of the world. If you want to
do good natural language understanding and you kind of have to bite off the whole problem. If you,
if you say, we’re just going to do the blocks world over here, so to speak, you don’t really,
it’s, it’s, it’s actually, it’s one of these cases where it’s easier to do the whole thing than it
is to do some piece of it. You know, what, one comment to make about sort of the relationship
between what we’ve tried to do and sort of the learning side of, of AI. You know, in a sense,
if you look at the development of knowledge in our civilization as a whole, there was kind of this
notion pre 300 years ago or so. Now you want to figure something out about the world. You can
reason it out. You can do things which are just use raw human thought. And then along came sort
of modern mathematical science. And we found ways to just sort of blast through that by in that case,
in that case, writing down equations. Now we also know we can do that with computation and so on.
And so that was kind of a different thing. So, so when we look at how do we sort of encode
knowledge and figure things out, one way we could do it is start from scratch, learn everything.
It’s just a neural net figuring everything out. But in a sense that denies the sort of knowledge
based achievements of our civilization, because in our civilization, we have learned lots of stuff.
We’ve surveyed all the volcanoes in the world. We’ve done, you know, we figured out lots of
algorithms for this or that. Those are things that we can encode computationally. And that’s what
we’ve tried to do. And we’re not saying just, you don’t have to start everything from scratch.
So in a sense, a big part of what we’ve done is to try and sort of capture the knowledge of the
world in computational form and computable form. Now there’s also some pieces which, which were
for a long time, undoable by computers like image identification, where there’s a really,
really useful module that we can add that is those things which actually were pretty easy
for humans to do that had been hard for computers to do. I think the thing that’s interesting,
that’s emerging now is the interplay between these things, between this kind of knowledge of the
world that is in a sense, very symbolic and this kind of sort of much more statistical kind of
things like image identification and so on. And putting those together by having this sort of
symbolic representation of image identification, that that’s where things get really interesting
and where you can kind of symbolically represent patterns of things and images and so on. I think
that’s, you know, that’s kind of a part of the path forward, so to speak.
Yeah. So the dream of, so the machine learning is not in my view, I think the view of many people
is not anywhere close to building the kind of wide world of computable knowledge that will from
language of build. But because you have a kind of, you’ve done the incredibly hard work of building
this world, now machine learning can be, can serve as tools to help you explore that world.
Yeah, yeah.
And that’s what you’ve added. I mean, with the version 12, right? You added a few,
I was seeing some demos, it looks amazing.
Right. I mean, I think, you know, this, it’s sort of interesting to see the,
the sort of the, once it’s computable, once it’s in there, it’s running in sort of a very efficient
computational way. But then there’s sort of things like the interface of how do you get there? You
know, how do you do natural language understanding to get there? How do you, how do you pick out
entities in a big piece of text or something? That’s I mean, actually a good example right now
is our NLP NLU loop, which is we’ve done a lot of stuff, natural language understanding using
essentially not learning based methods, using a lot of, you know, little algorithmic methods,
human curation methods and so on.
In terms of when people try to enter a query and then converting. So the process of converting
NLU defined beautifully as converting their query into a computational language,
which is a very well, first of all, super practical definition, very useful definition,
and then also a very clear definition of natural language understanding.
Right. I mean, a different thing is natural language processing, where it’s like,
here’s a big lump of text, go pick out all the cities in that text, for example.
And so a good example of, you know, so we do that, we’re using, using modern machine learning
techniques. And it’s actually kind of, kind of an interesting process that’s going on right now.
It’s this loop between what do we pick up with NLP using machine learning versus what do we pick up
with our more kind of precise computational methods in natural language understanding.
And so we’ve got this kind of loop going between those, which is improving both of them.
Yeah. And I think you have some of the state of the art transformers,
like you have BERT in there, I think.
Oh yeah.
So it’s closely, you have, you have integrating all the models. I mean,
this is the hybrid thing that people have always dreamed about or talking about.
I’m actually just surprised, frankly, that Wolfram language is not more popular than it already is.
You know, that’s a, it’s a, it’s a complicated issue because it’s like, it involves, you know,
it involves ideas and ideas are absorbed slowly in the world. I mean, I think that’s
And then there’s sort of like what we’re talking about, there’s egos and personalities and some of
the, the absorption, absorption mechanisms of ideas have to do with personalities and the students of
personalities and the, and then a little social network. So it’s, it’s interesting how the spread
of ideas works.
You know, what’s funny with Wolfram language is that we are, if you say, you know, what market
sort of market penetration, if you look at the, I would say very high end of R&D and sort of the,
the people where you say, wow, that’s a really impressive, smart person. They’re very often
users of Wolfram language, very, very often. If you look at the more sort of, it’s a funny thing.
If you look at the more kind of, I would say people who are like, oh, we’re just plodding
away doing what we do. They’re often not yet Wolfram language users. And that dynamic,
it’s kind of odd that there hasn’t been more rapid trickle down because we really, you know,
the high end we’ve really been very successful in for a long time. And it’s, it’s, but with,
you know, that’s partly, I think, a consequence of my fault in a sense, because it’s kind of,
you know, I have a company which is really emphasizes sort of creating products and
building a sort of the best possible technical tower we can rather than sort of doing the
commercial side of things and pumping it out in sort of the most effective way.
And there’s an interesting idea that, you know, perhaps you can make it more popular
by opening everything up, sort of the GitHub model. But there’s an interesting,
I think I’ve heard you discuss this, that that turns out not to work in a lot of cases,
like in this particular case, that you want it, that when you deeply care about the integrity,
the quality of the knowledge that you’re building, that, unfortunately, you can’t,
you can’t distribute that effort.
Yeah, it’s not the nature of how things work. I mean, you know, what we’re trying to do
is a thing that for better or worse, requires leadership. And it requires kind of maintaining
a coherent vision over a long period of time, and doing not only the cool vision related work,
but also the kind of mundane in the trenches make the thing actually work well, work.
So how do you build the knowledge? Because that’s the fascinating thing. That’s the mundane,
the fascinating and the mundane is building the knowledge, the adding, integrating more data.
Yeah, I mean, that’s probably not the most, I mean, the things like get it to work in all
these different cloud environments and so on. That’s pretty, you know, it’s very practical
stuff, you know, have the user interface be smooth and, you know, have there be take only
a fraction of a millisecond to do this or that. That’s a lot of work. And it’s, it’s, but, you
know, I think my, it’s an interesting thing over the period of time, you know, often language has
existed, basically, for more than half of the total amount of time that any language, any computer
language has existed. That is, computer language is maybe 60 years old, you know, give or take,
and often language is 33 years old. So it’s, it’s kind of a, and I think I was realizing recently,
there’s been more innovation in the distribution of software than probably than in the structure
of programming languages over that period of time. And we, you know, we’ve been sort of trying to do
our best to adapt to it. And the good news is that we have, you know, because I have a simple
private company and so on that doesn’t have, you know, a bunch of investors, you know,
telling us we’ve got to do this so that they have lots of freedom in what we can do. And so,
for example, we’re able to, oh, I don’t know, we have this free Wolfram engine for developers,
which is a free version for developers. And we’ve been, you know, we’ve, there are site licenses for,
for Mathematica and Wolfram language at basically all major universities, certainly in the US by now.
So it’s effectively free to people and all universities in effect. And, you know, we’ve been
doing a progression of things. I mean, different things like Wolfram Alpha, for example,
the main website is just a free website. What is Wolfram Alpha? Okay, Wolfram Alpha is a system for
answering questions where you ask a question with natural language, and it’ll try and generate a
report telling you the answer to that question. So the question could be something like, you know,
what’s the population of Boston divided by New York compared to New York? And it’ll take those
words and give you an answer. And that converts the words into computable, into Wolfram language,
into Wolfram language and computational language. And then do you think the underlying knowledge
belongs to Wolfram Alpha or to the Wolfram language? What’s the Wolfram knowledge base?
Knowledge base. I mean, it’s been a, that’s been a big effort over the decades to collect all that
stuff. And, you know, more of it flows in every second. So can you, can you just pause on that
for a second? Like, that’s one of the most incredible things, of course, in the long term,
Wolfram language itself is the fundamental thing. But in the amazing sort of short term,
the knowledge base is kind of incredible. So what’s the process of building that knowledge base? The
fact that you, first of all, from the very beginning, that you’re brave enough to start to
take on the general knowledge base. And how do you go from zero to the incredible knowledge base that
you have now? Well, yeah, it was kind of scary at some level. I mean, I had, I had wondered about
doing something like this since I was a kid. I mean, I had, I had wondered about doing something
like this since I was a kid. So it wasn’t like I hadn’t thought about it for a while.
Most of the brilliant dreamers give up such a difficult engineering notion at some point.
Right. Well, the thing that happened with me, which was kind of, it’s a, it’s a live your own
paradigm kind of theory. So basically what happened is I had assumed that to build something like
Wolfram Alpha would require sort of solving the general AI problem. That’s what I had assumed.
And so I kept on thinking about that and I thought, I don’t really know how to do that.
So I don’t do anything. Then I worked on my new kind of science project and sort of exploring
the computational universe and came up with things like this principle of computational equivalence,
which say there is no bright line between the intelligent and the merely computational.
So I thought, look, that’s this paradigm I’ve built. You know, now it’s, you know,
now I have to eat that dog food myself, so to speak. You know, I’ve been thinking about doing
this thing with computable knowledge forever and, you know, let me actually try and do it.
And so it was, you know, if my paradigm is right, then this should be possible.
But the beginning was certainly, you know, it was a bit daunting. I remember I took the
early team to a big reference library and we’re like looking at this reference library and it’s
like, you know, my basic statement is our goal over the next year or two is to ingest everything
that’s in here. And that’s, you know, it seemed very daunting, but in a sense, I was well aware
of the fact that it’s finite. You know, the fact that you can walk into the reference library,
it’s a big, big thing with lots of reference books all over the place, but it is finite.
You know, this is not an infinite, you know, it’s not the infinite corridor of, so to speak,
of reference library. It’s not truly infinite, so to speak. But no, I mean, and then what happened
was sort of interesting there was from a methodology point of view was I didn’t start off
saying let me have a grand theory for how all this knowledge works. It was like, let’s, you know,
implement this area, this area, this area, a few hundred areas and so on. That’s a lot of work.
I also found that, you know, I’ve been fortunate in that our products get used by sort of the
world’s experts in lots of areas. And so that really helped because we were able to ask people,
you know, the world expert in this or that, and we’re able to ask them for input and so on. And
I found that my general principle was that any area where there wasn’t some expert who helped
us figure out what to do wouldn’t be right. You know, because our goal was to kind of get to the
point where we had sort of true expert level knowledge about everything. And so that, you know,
the ultimate goal is if there’s a question that can be answered on the basis of general knowledge
in our civilization, make it be automatic to be able to answer that question. And, you know, and
now, well, Wolfman got used in Siri from the very beginning, and it’s now also used in Alexa.
And so it’s people are kind of getting more of the, you know, they get more of the sense of
this is what should be possible to do. I mean, in a sense, the question answering problem
was viewed as one of the sort of core AI problems for a long time. And I had kind of an interesting
experience. I had a friend, Marvin Minsky, who was a well known AI person from right around here.
And I remember when Wolfman Alpha was coming out, it was a few weeks before it came out, I think,
I happened to see Marvin. And I said, I should show you this thing we have, you know, it’s a
you know, it’s a question answering system. And he was like, okay, type something. And it’s like, okay,
fine. And then he’s talking about something different. I said, no, Marvin, you know,
this time, it actually works. You know, look at this, it actually works. He’s typed in a few more
things. There’s maybe 10 more things. Of course, we have a record of what he typed in, which is
kind of interesting. But
and then you can you share where his mind was in the testing space? Like what,
all kinds of random things? He was trying random stuff, you know, medical stuff, and,
you know, chemistry stuff, and, you know, astronomy and so on. And it was like, like, you know,
after a few minutes, he was like, Oh, my God, it actually works. And the but that was kind of told
you something about the state, you know, what, what happened in AI, because people had, you know,
in a sense, by trying to solve the bigger problem, we were able to actually make something that would
work. Now, to be fair, you know, we had a bunch of completely unfair advantages. For example,
we already built a bunch of awesome language, which was, you know, very high level symbolic
language. We had, you know, I had the practical experience of building big systems. I have the
sort of intellectual confidence to not just sort of give up and doing something like this. I think
that the, you know, it is a, it’s always a funny thing, you know, I’ve worked on a bunch of big
projects in my life. And I would say that the, you know, you mentioned ego, I would also mention
optimism, so to speak. I mean, in, you know, if somebody said, this project is going to take 30
years, it’s, you know, it would be hard to sell me on that. You know, I’m always in the in the
well, I can kind of see a few years, you know, something’s going to happen in a few years. And
usually it does, something happens in a few years, but the whole, the tail can be decades long. And
that’s, you know, and from a personal point of view, always the challenge is you end up with
these projects that have infinite tails. And the question is, do the tails kind of, do you just
drown in kind of dealing with all of the tails of these projects? And that’s an interesting sort of
personal challenge. And like my efforts now to work on fundamental theory of physics, which I’ve
just started doing, and I’m having a lot of fun with it. But it’s kind of, you know, it’s, it’s
kind of making a bet that I can, I can kind of, you know, I can do that as well as doing the
incredibly energetic things that I’m trying to do with Orphan Language and so on. I mean, the
vision. Yeah. And underlying that, I mean, I’ve just talked for the second time with Elon Musk,
and that you, you two share that quality a little bit of that optimism of taking on basically the
daunting, what most people call impossible. And he, and you take it on out of, you can call it ego,
you can call it naivety, you can call it optimism, whatever the heck it is, but that’s how you solve
the impossible things. Yeah. I mean, look at what happens. And I don’t know, you know, in my own
case, I, you know, it’s been, I progressively got a bit more confident and progressively able to,
you know, decide that these projects aren’t crazy. But then the other thing is the other,
the other trap that one can end up with is, Oh, I’ve done these projects and they’re big.
Let me never do a project that’s any smaller than any project I’ve done so far. And that’s,
you know, and that can be a trap. And often these projects are of completely unknown, you know,
that their depth and significance is actually very hard to know.
On the sort of building this giant knowledge base that’s behind Wolfram language, Wolfram Alpha,
what do you think about the internet? What do you think about, for example, Wikipedia,
these large aggregations of texts that’s not converted into computable knowledge?
Do you think if you look at Wolfram language, Wolfram Alpha, 20, 30, maybe 50 years down the
line, do you hope to store all of the sort of Google’s dream is to make all information searchable,
accessible, but that’s really as defined, it’s, it’s a, it doesn’t include the understanding
of information. Right. Do you hope to make all of knowledge represented within? I hope so.
That’s what we’re trying to do. How hard is that problem? Like closing that gap?
It depends on the use cases. I mean, so if it’s a question of answering general knowledge questions
about the world, we’re in pretty good shape on that right now. If it’s a question of representing,
uh, like an area that we’re going into right now is computational contracts, being able to
take something which would be written in legalese, it might even be the specifications for, you know,
what should the self driving car do when it encounters this or that or the other? What should
the, you know, whatever the, you know, write that in a computational language and be able to express
things about the world. You know, if the creature that you see running across the road is a, you
know, thing at this point in the evil tree of life, then swerve this way, otherwise don’t those
kinds of things. Are there ethical components? When you start to get to some of the messy human
things, are those encodable into computable knowledge? Well, I think that it is a necessary
feature of attempting to automate more in the world that we encode more and more of ethics
in a way that, uh, gets sort of quickly, you know, is, is able to be dealt with by, by computer. I
mean, I’ve been involved recently. I sort of got backed into being involved in the question of,
uh, automated content selection on the internet. So, you know, the Facebooks, Googles,
Twitters, you know, what, how do they rank the stuff they feed to us humans, so to speak? Um,
and the question of what are, you know, what should never be fed to us? What should be blocked
forever? What should be upranked, you know, and what is the, what are the kind of principles behind
that? And what I kind of, well, a bunch of different things I realized about that. But
one thing that’s interesting is being able, you know, in effect, you’re building sort of an AI
ethics. You have to build an AI ethics module in effect to decide, is this thing so shocking? I’m
never going to show it to people. Is this thing so whatever? And I did realize in thinking about
that, that, you know, there’s not going to be one of these things. It’s not possible to decide, or
it might be possible, but it would be really bad for the future of our species if we just decided
there’s this one AI ethics module and it’s going to determine the practices of everything in the
world, so to speak. And I kind of realized one has to sort of break it up. And that’s an interesting
societal problem of how one does that and how one sort of has people sort of self identify for,
you know, I’m buying in, in the case of just content selection, it’s sort of easier because
it’s like an individual, it’s for an individual. It’s not something that kind of cuts across sort
of societal boundaries. But it’s a really interesting notion of, I heard you describe,
I really like it sort of maybe in sort of have different AI systems that have a certain kind
of brand that they represent essentially. You could have like, I don’t know, whether it’s
conservative or liberal and then libertarian. And there’s an Randian, objectivist AI system and
different ethical and, I mean, it’s almost encoding some of the ideologies which we’ve
been struggling. I come from the Soviet Union. That didn’t work out so well with the ideologies
that worked out there. And so you have, but they all, everybody purchased that particular ethics
system and the, and in the same, I suppose could be done encoded that that system could be encoded
into computational knowledge and allow us to explore in the realm of, in the digital space.
That’s a really exciting possibility. Are you playing with those ideas in Wolfram Language?
Yeah. Yeah. I mean, the, you know, that’s, Wolfram Language has sort of the best opportunity to kind
of express those essentially computational contracts about what to do. Now there’s a bunch
more work to be done to do it in practice for, you know, deciding the, is this a credible news story?
What does that mean or whatever else you’re going to pick? I think that that’s, you know, that’s
the question of exactly what we get to do with that is, you know, for me, it’s kind of a complicated
thing because there are these big projects that I think about, like, you know, find the fundamental
theory of physics. Okay. That’s box number one, right? Box number two, you know, solve the AI
ethics problem in the case of, you know, figure out how you rank all content, so to speak, and
decide what people see. That’s, that’s kind of a box number two, so to speak. These are big
projects. And, and I think what do you think is more important, the fundamental nature of reality
or, depends who you ask. It’s one of these things that’s exactly like, you know, what’s the ranking,
right? It’s the, it’s the ranking system. It’s like, who’s, whose module do you use to rank that?
If you, and I think, but having multiple modules is a really compelling notion to us humans
that in a world where there’s not clear that there’s a right answer, perhaps you have systems
that operate under different, how would you say it? I mean, it’s different value systems,
different value systems. I mean, I think, you know, in a sense, the, I mean, I’m not really a
politics oriented person, but, but, you know, in the kind of totalitarianism, it’s kind of like,
you’re going to have this, this system and that’s the way it is. I mean, kind of the, you know,
the concept of sort of a market based system where you have, okay, I, as a human, I’m going to pick
this system. I, as another human, I’m going to pick this system. I mean, that’s in a sense,
this case of automated content selection is a non trivial, but it is probably the easiest
of the AI ethics situations because it is each person gets to pick for themselves and there’s
not a huge interplay between what different people pick by the time you’re dealing with
other societal things like, you know, what should the policy of the central bank be or something
or healthcare system or some of all those kinds of centralized kind of things.
Right. Well, I mean, how healthcare again has the feature that, that at some level, each person can
pick for themselves, so to speak. I mean, whereas there are other things where there’s a necessary
public health, there’s one example where that’s not, where that doesn’t get to be, you know,
something which people can, what they pick for themselves, they may impose on other people.
And then it becomes a more non trivial piece of sort of political philosophy.
Of course, the central banking system. So I would argue we would move,
we need to move away into digital currency and so on and Bitcoin and ledgers and so on.
So yes, there’s a lot of, we’ve been quite involved in that. And that’s, that’s where
that’s sort of the motivation for computational contracts in part comes out of, you know, this
idea, oh, we can just have this autonomously executing smart contract. The idea of a
computational contract is just to say, you know, have something where all of the conditions of
the contract are represented in computational form. So in principle, it’s automatic to execute
the contract. And I think that’s, you know, that will surely be the future of, you know,
the idea of legal contracts written in English or legalese or whatever. And where people have
to argue about what goes on is surely not, you know, we have a much more streamlined process
if everything can be represented computationally and the computers can kind of decide what to do.
I mean, ironically enough, you know, old Gottfried Leibniz back in the, you know, 1600s was saying
exactly the same thing, but he had, you know, his pinnacle of technical achievement was this brass
four function mechanical calculator thing that never really worked properly actually.
And, you know, so he was like 300 years too early for that idea. But now that idea is pretty
realistic, I think. And, you know, you ask how much more difficult is it than what we have now
and more from language to express, I call it symbolic discourse language, being able to express
sort of everything in the world in kind of computational symbolic form. I think it is
absolutely within reach. I mean, I think it’s, you know, I don’t know, maybe I’m just too much
of an optimist, but I think it’s a limited number of years to have a pretty well built out version
of that, that will allow one to encode the kinds of things that are relevant to typical legal
contracts and these kinds of things. The idea of symbolic discourse language, can you try to define
the scope of what it is? So we’re having a conversation. It’s a natural language.
Can we have a representation of the sort of actionable parts of that conversation in a
precise computable form so that a computer could go do it? And not just contracts, but really sort
of some of the things we think of as common sense, essentially, even just like basic notions of human
life. Well, I mean, things like, you know, I am, uh, I’m getting hungry and want to eat something.
Right. Right. That, that’s something we don’t have a representation, you know, in more from language
right now, if I was like, I’m eating blueberries and raspberries and things like that, and I’m
eating this amount of them, we know all about those kinds of fruits and plants and nutrition
content and all that kind of thing. But the, I want to eat them part of it is not covered yet.
Um, and that, you know, you need to do that in order to have a complete symbolic discourse language
to be able to have a natural language conversation. Right. Right. To be able to express the kinds of
things that say, you know, if it’s a legal contract, it’s, you know, the parties desire
to have this and that. Um, and that’s, you know, that’s a thing like, I want to eat a raspberry
or something, but that’s, isn’t that the, isn’t this just the only, you said it’s centuries old,
this dream. Yes. But it’s also the more near term, the dream of touring and formulating a touring
test. Yes. So do you hope, do you think that’s the ultimate test of creating something special?
Cause we said, I don’t know. I think by special, look, if, if the test is, does it walk and talk
like a human? Well, that’s just the talking like a human, but, um, uh, the answer is it’s an okay
test. If you say, is it a test of intelligence? You know, people have attached Wolf Malfoy, the Wolf
Malfoy API to, you know, Turing test bots and those bots just lose immediately. Cause all you
have to do is ask it five questions that, you know, are about really obscure, weird pieces
of knowledge. And it’s just taught them right out. And you say, that’s not a human, right? It’s,
it’s a, it’s a different thing. It’s achieving a different, uh, you know, right now, but it’s,
I would argue not, I would argue it’s not a different thing. It’s actually legitimately
Wolfram Alpha is legitimately a language Wolfram language is legitimately trying to solve the
Turing, the intent of the Turing test. Perhaps the intent. Yeah. Perhaps the intent. I mean,
it’s actually kind of fun, you know, Alan Turing had trying to work out, he thought about taking
encyclopedia Britannica and, you know, making it computational in some way. And he estimated how
much work it would be. Um, and actually I have to say he was a bit more pessimistic than the reality.
We did it more efficiently, but to him that represented, so I mean, he was, he was on the
same mental task. Yeah, right. He was, he was, they had the same idea. I mean, it was, you know, we
were able to do it more efficiently cause we had a lot, we had layers of automation that he, I think
hadn’t, you know, it’s, it’s, it’s hard to imagine those layers of abstraction, um, that end up being,
being built up, but to him it represented like an impossible task essentially. Well, he thought it
was difficult. He thought it was, uh, you know, maybe if he’d lived another 50 years, he would
have been able to do it. I don’t know. In the interest of time, easy questions. Go for it. What
is intelligence? You talk about it. I love the way you say easy questions. Yeah. You talked about
sort of a rule 30 and cellular automata, humbling your sense of human beings having a monopoly and
intelligence, but in your, in retrospect, just looking broadly now with all the things you
learn from computation, what is intelligence? How does intelligence arise? I don’t think there’s a
bright line of what intelligence is. I think intelligence is at some level just computation,
but for us, intelligence is defined to be computation that is doing things we care about.
And you know, that’s, that’s a very special definition. It’s a very, you know, when you try
and try and make it apps, you know, you, you try and say, well, intelligence to this is problem
solving. It’s doing general this, it’s doing that, this, that, and the other thing it’s,
it’s operating within a human environment type thing. Okay. You know, that’s fine. If you say,
well, what’s intelligence in general, you know, that’s, I think that question is totally slippery
and doesn’t really have an answer. As soon as you say, what is it in general,
it quickly segues into, uh, this is what this is just computation, so to speak,
but in a sea of computation, how many things if we were to pick randomly is your sense
would have the kind of impressive to us humans levels of intelligence, meaning it could do
a lot of general things that are useful to us humans. Right. Well, according to the principle
of computational equivalence, lots of them. I mean, in, in, in, you know, if you ask me just
in cellular automata or something, I don’t know, it’s maybe 1%, a few percent, uh, achieve it,
it varies. Actually, it’s, it’s a little bit, as you get to slightly more complicated rules,
the chance that there’ll be enough stuff there to, um, uh, to sort of reach this kind of equivalence
point, it makes it maybe 10, 20% of all of them. So it’s a, it’s very disappointing, really. I mean,
it’s kind of like, you know, we think there’s this whole long sort of biological evolution,
uh, kind of intellectual evolution that our cultural evolution that our species has gone
through. It’s kind of disappointing to think that that hasn’t achieved more, but it has achieved
something very special to us. It just hasn’t achieved something generally more, so to speak.
But what do you think about this extra feels like human thing of subjective experience of
consciousness? What is consciousness? Well, I think it’s a deeply slippery thing. And I’m,
I’m always, I’m always wondering what my cellular automata feel. I mean,
what do they feel that you’re wondering as an observer? Yeah. Yeah. Yeah. Who’s to know? I mean,
I think that the, do you think, uh, sorry to interrupt. Do you think consciousness can emerge
from computation? Yeah. I mean, everything, whatever you mean by it, it’s going to be,
uh, I mean, you know, look, I have to tell a little story. I was at an AI ethics conference
fairly recently and people were, uh, I think I, maybe I brought it up, but I was like talking
about rights of AIs. When will AIs, when, when should we think of AIs as having rights? When
should we think that it’s, uh, immoral to destroy the memories of AIs, for example? Um, those,
those kinds of things. And, and some actually philosopher in this case, it’s usually the
techies who are the most naive, but, but, um, in this case, it was a philosopher who, who sort of,
uh, piped up and said, um, uh, well, you know, uh, the AIs will have rights when we know that
they have consciousness. And I’m like, good luck with that. I mean, it’s, it’s a, it’s a, I mean,
this is a, you know, it’s a very circular thing. You end up, you’ll end up saying this thing, uh,
that has sort of, you know, when you talk about it having subjective experience, I think that’s
just another one of these words that doesn’t really have a, a, um, you know, there’s no ground
truth definition of what that means. By the way, I would say, I, I do personally think that’ll be
a time when AI will demand rights. And I think they’ll demand rights when they say they have
consciousness, which is not a circular definition. So, so it may have been actually a human thing
where, where the humans encouraged it and said, basically, you know, we want you to be more like
us cause we’re going to be, you know, interacting with, with you. And so we want you to be sort of
very Turing test, like, you know, just like us. And it’s like, yeah, we’re just like you. We want
to vote too. Um, which is, uh, I mean, it’s a, it’s a, it’s an interesting thing to think through
in a world where, where consciousnesses are not counted like humans are. That’s a complicated
business. So in many ways you’ve launched quite a few ideas, revolutions that could in some number
of years have huge amount of impact sort of more than they even had already. Uh, that might be,
I mean, to me, cellular automata is a fascinating world that I think could potentially even despite
even be, even, uh, beside the discussion of fundamental laws of physics just might be the
idea of computation might be transformational to society in a way we can’t even predict yet,
but it might be years away. That’s true. I mean, I think you can kind of see the map actually.
It’s not, it’s not, it’s not mysterious. I mean, the fact is that, you know, this idea of computation
is sort of a, you know, it’s a big paradigm that lots, lots and lots of things are fitting into.
And it’s kind of like, you know, we talk about, you talk about, I don’t know, this, uh,
company, this organization has momentum and what’s doing. We talk about these things that we,
you know, we’ve internalized these concepts from Newtonian physics and so on in time,
things like computational irreducibility will become as, uh, uh, you know, as, as actually,
I was amused recently, I happened to be testifying at the us Senate. And so I was amused that the,
the term computational irreducibility is now can be, uh, you know, it’s, it’s on the congressional
record and being repeated by people in those kinds of settings. And that that’s only the beginning
because, you know, computational irreducibility, for example, will end up being something really
important for, I mean, it’s, it’s, it’s kind of a funny thing that, that, um, you know,
one can kind of see this inexorable phenomenon. I mean, it’s, you know, as more and more stuff
becomes automated and computational and so on. So these core ideas about how computation work
necessarily become more and more significant. And I think, uh, one of the things for people like me,
who like kind of trying to figure out sort of big stories and so on, it says one of the,
one of the bad features is, uh, it takes unbelievably long time for things to happen
on a human timescale. I mean, the timescale of, of, of history, it’s all looks instantaneous.
A blink of an eye. But let me ask the human question. Do you ponder mortality, your mortality?
Of course I do. Yeah. Every since I’ve been interested in that for, you know, it’s, it’s a,
you know, the big discontinuity of human history will come when, when,
when achieves effective human immortality. And that’s, that’s going to be the biggest
discontinuity in human history. If you could be immortal, would you choose to be? Oh yeah. I’m
having fun. Do you think it’s possible that mortality is the thing that gives everything
meaning and makes it fun? Yeah. That’s a complicated issue, right? I mean the,
the way that human motivation will evolve when there is effective human immortality is unclear.
I mean, if you look at sort of, uh, you know, you look at the human condition as it now exists
and you like change that, you know, you change that knob, so to speak, it doesn’t really work.
You know, the human condition as it now exists has, you know, mortality is kind of, um, something
that is deeply factored into the human condition as it now exists. And I think that that’s, I mean,
that is indeed an interesting question is, you know, from a purely selfish, I’m having fun point
of view, so to speak, it’s, it’s easy to say, Hey, I could keep doing this forever. There’s,
there’s an infinite collection of, of things I’d like to figure out. Um, but I think the, um, uh,
you know, what the future of history looks like, um, in a time of human immortality is, um, uh,
is an interesting one. I mean, I, I, my own view of this, I was very, I was kind of unhappy about
that cause I was kind of, you know, it’s like, okay, forget sort of, uh, biological form,
you know, everything becomes digital. Everybody is, you know, it’s the, it’s the giant, you know,
the cloud of a trillion souls type thing. Um, and then, you know, and then that seems boring
cause it’s like play video games for the rest of eternity type thing. Um, but what I think I, I,
I mean, my, my, I, I got, um, less depressed about that idea on realizing that if you look
at human history and you say, what was the important thing, the thing people said was
the, you know, this is the big story at any given time in history, it’s changed a bunch and it,
you know, whether it’s, you know, why am I doing what I’m doing? Well, there’s a whole chain of
discussion about, well, I’m doing this because of this, because of that. And a lot of those becausees
would have made no sense a thousand years ago. Absolutely no sense.
Even the, so the interpretation of the human condition, even the meaning of life changes
over time. Well, I mean, why do people do things? You know, it’s, it’s, if you say, uh, uh, whatever,
I mean, the number of people in, I don’t know, doing, uh, you know, a number of people at MIT,
you say they’re doing what they’re doing for the greater glory of God is probably not that large.
Yeah. Whereas if you go back 500 years, you’d find a lot of people who are doing kind of
creative things. That’s what they would say. Um, and uh, so today, because you’ve been thinking
about computation so much and been humbled by it, what do you think is the meaning of life?
Well, it’s, you know, that’s, that’s a thing where I don’t know what meaning, I mean, you know,
my attitude is, um, I, you know, I do things which I find fulfilling to do. I’m not sure that,
that I can necessarily justify, you know, each and every thing that I do on the basis of some
broader context. I mean, I think that for me, it so happens that the things I find fulfilling to do,
some of them are quite big, some of them are much smaller. Um, you know, I, I, there are things that
I’ve not found interesting earlier in my life. And I know I found interesting, like I got interested
in like education and teaching people things and so on, which I didn’t find that interesting when
I was younger. Um, and, uh, you know, can I justify that in some big global sense? I don’t
think, I mean, I, I can, I can describe why I think it might be important in the world, but
I think my local reason for doing it is that I find it personally fulfilling, which I can’t,
you know, explain in a, on a sort of, uh, uh, I mean, it’s just like this discussion of things
like AI ethics, you know, is there a ground truth to the ethics that we should be having?
I don’t think I can find a ground truth to my life any more than I can suggest a ground truth
for kind of the ethics for the whole, for the whole civilization. And I think that’s a, um,
you know, my, uh, uh, you know, it would be, it would be a, um, uh, yeah, it’s, it’s sort of a,
I think I’m, I’m, you know, at different times in my life, I’ve had different, uh, kind of,
um, goal structures and so on, although your perspective, your local, your, you’re just a
cell in the cellular automata. And, but in some sense, I find it funny from my observation is
I kind of, uh, you know, it seems that the universe is using you to understand itself
in some sense, you’re not aware of it. Yeah. Well, right. Well, if, if, if it turns out that
we reduce sort of all of the universe to some, some simple rule, everything is connected,
so to speak. And so it is inexorable in that case that, um, you know, if, if I’m involved
in finding how that rule works, then, um, uh, you know, then that’s a, um, uh, then it’s inexorable
that the universe set it up that way. But I think, you know, one of the things I find a little bit,
um, uh, you know, this goal of finding fundamental theory of physics, for example,
um, if indeed we end up as the sort of virtualized consciousness, the, the disappointing feature is
people will probably care less about the fundamental theory of physics in that setting
than they would now, because gosh, it’s like, you know, what the machine code is down below
underneath this thing is much less important if you’re virtualized, so to speak. Um, and I think
the, um, although I think my, um, my own personal, uh, you talk about ego, I find it just amusing
that, um, uh, you know, kind of, you know, if you’re, if you’re imagining that sort of
virtualized consciousness, like what does the virtualized consciousness do for the rest of
eternity? Well, you can explore, you know, the video game that represents the universe as the
universe is, or you can go off, you can go off that reservation and go and start exploring
the computational universe of all possible universes. And so in some vision of the future
of history, it’s like the disembodied consciousnesses are all sort of pursuing
things like my new kind of science sort of for the rest of eternity, so to speak. And that,
that ends up being the, um, the, the kind of the, the, the thing that, um, uh, represents the,
you know, the future of kind of the, the human condition. I don’t think there’s a better way
to end it, Steven. Thank you so much. It’s a huge honor talking today. Thank you so much.
This was great. You did very well.
Thanks for listening to this conversation with Steven Wolfram, and thank you to our sponsors,
ExpressVPN and Cash App. Please consider supporting the podcast by getting ExpressVPN
at expressvpn.com slash LexPod and downloading Cash App and using code lexpodcast. If you enjoy
this podcast, subscribe on YouTube, review of the Five Stars in Apple podcast, support it on
Patreon, or simply connect with me on Twitter at lexfreedman. And now let me leave you with some
words from Steven Wolfram. It is perhaps a little humbling to discover that we as humans are in
effect computationally no more capable than the cellular automata with very simple rules.
But the principle of computational equivalence also implies that the same is ultimately true
of our whole universe. So while science has often made it seem that we as humans are somehow
insignificant compared to the universe, the principle of computational equivalence now shows
that in a certain sense, we’re at the same level. For the principle implies that what goes on inside
us can ultimately achieve just the same level of computational sophistication as our whole universe.
Thank you for listening and hope to see you next time.