Lex Fridman Podcast - #124 - Stephen Wolfram: Fundamental Theory of Physics, Life, and the Universe

The following is a conversation with Stephen Wolfram,

his second time on the podcast.

He’s a computer scientist, mathematician,

theoretical physicist, and the founder and CEO

of Wolfram Research, a company behind Mathematica,

Wolfram Alpha, Wolfram Language,

and the new Wolfram Physics Project.

He’s the author of several books,

including A New Kind of Science, and the new book,

A Project to Find the Fundamental Theory of Physics.

This second round of our conversation is primarily focused

on this latter endeavor of searching for the physics

of our universe in simple rules that do their work

on hypergraphs and eventually generate the infrastructure

from which space, time, and all of modern physics can emerge.

Quick summary of the sponsors,

SimpliSafe, Sunbasket, and Masterclass.

Please check out these sponsors in the description

to get a discount and to support this podcast.

As a side note, let me say that to me,

the idea that seemingly infinite complexity can arise

from very simple rules and initial conditions

is one of the most beautiful and important

mathematical and philosophical mysteries in science.

I find that both cellular automata

and the hypergraph data structure

that Stephen and team are currently working on

to be the kind of simple, clear mathematical playground

within which fundamental ideas about intelligence,

consciousness, and the fundamental laws of physics

can be further developed in totally new ways.

In fact, I think I’ll try to make a video or two

about the most beautiful aspects of these models

in the coming weeks, especially, I think,

trying to describe how fellow curious minds like myself

can jump in and explore them either just for fun

or potentially for publication of new innovative research

in math, computer science, and physics.

But honestly, I think the emerging complexity

in these hypergraphs can capture the imagination

of everyone, even if you’re someone

who never really connected with mathematics.

That’s my hope, at least, to have these conversations

that inspire everyone to look up to the skies

and into our own minds in awe of our amazing universe.

Let me also mention that this is the first time

I ever recorded a podcast outdoors

as a kind of experiment to see if this is an option

in times of COVID.

I’m sorry if the audio is not great.

I did my best and promise to keep improving

and learning as always.

If you enjoy this thing, subscribe on YouTube,

review it with Five Stars and Apple Podcast,

follow on Spotify, support on Patreon,

or connect with me on Twitter at Lex Friedman.

As usual, I’ll do a few minutes of ads now

and no ads in the middle.

I tried to make these interesting,

but I do give you timestamps, so you’re welcome to skip,

but still, please do check out the sponsors

by clicking the links in the description.

It’s the best way to support this podcast.

Also, let me say, even though I’m talking way too much,

that I did a survey and it seems like over 90% of people

either enjoy these ad reads somehow magically

or don’t mind them, at least.

That honestly just warms my heart

that people are that supportive.

This show is sponsored by SimpliSafe,

a home security company.

Go to SimpliSafe.com to get a free HD camera.

It’s simple, no contracts, 15 bucks a month, easy setup.

Even I figured it out.

I have it set up in my apartment.

Of course, I also welcome intruders.

One of my favorite movies is Leon or The Professional

with Jean Reno, Gary Oldman,

and the brilliant young Natalie Portman.

If you haven’t seen the movie,

he’s a hit man with a minimalist life that resembles my own.

In fact, when I was younger, the idea of being a hit man

or targeting evil in a skilled way,

which is how I thought about it, really appealed to me.

The skill of it, the planning, the craftsmanship.

In another life, perhaps,

if I didn’t love engineering and science so much,

I could see myself being something like a Navy SEAL.

And in general, I love the idea of serving my country,

of serving society by contributing my skill

in some small way.

Anyway, go to Simplisafe.com slash Lex

to get a free HD camera and to support this podcast.

They’re a new sponsor, and this is a trial run,

so you know what to do.

This show is also sponsored by Sun Basket,

a meal delivery service.

Visit SunBasket.com slash Lex

and use code LEX to get $30 off your order

and to support this podcast.

This is the last read of the trial they’re doing,

so this is the time to get them if you’re considering it.

And if you do, it’ll help ensure

that they decide to support this podcast long term.

Their meals are healthy and delicious,

a nice break from the minimalist meals of meat

and vegetables that I usually eat.

Maybe on a personal note,

one of my favorite things to do is watch people cook,

especially people who love cooking,

and hang out with people over amazing meals.

I still tend to be strict in my diet no matter what,

even in fancy restaurants,

but it brings me joy to see friends and family indulge

something like a cake that has way too many calories

or ice cream or whatever.

My mom, in fact, for much of my life,

made this cake called an anthill on my birthday

that brings me a lot of joy and way too many calories.

I was thinking of doing a video with my mom as she makes it.

I thought it’d be a fun thing to do together.

Anyway, go to SunBasket.com slash Lex and use code LEX.

Do it now.

So they signed a longterm contract for this podcast.

This show is also sponsored by Masterclass.

Sign up at masterclass.com slash LEX.

180 bucks a year, you get an all access pass

to watch lessons from Chris Hadfield,

Neil deGrasse Tyson, Tony Hawk, Carlos Santana,

Garrett Casparov, Daniel Nagano,

and many more brilliant world experts.

Masterclass has been a really special sponsor.

They believe in this podcast in a way that gives me strength

and motivation to take intellectual risks.

I’m thinking of doing a few solo podcast episodes

on difficult topics, especially in history,

like the rise and fall of the Third Reich or Stalin, Putin,

and many other difficult topics that I’m fascinated by.

I have a worldview that seeks inspiring positive insights,

even and perhaps especially from periods of tragedy and evil

that perhaps some folks may find value in.

If I can only learn to convey the ideas in my mind

as clearly as I think them.

I think deeply and rigorously and precisely,

but to be honest, have trouble speaking in a way

that reflects that rigor of thought.

So it really does mean a lot, the love and support I get

as I try to get better at this thing,

at this talking thing.

Anyway, go to masterclass.com slash LEX to get a discount

and to support this podcast.

And now finally, here’s my conversation with Stephen Wolfram.

You said that there are moments in history of physics

and maybe mathematical physics or even mathematics

where breakthroughs happen

and then a flurry of progress follows.

So if you look back through the history of physics,

what moments stand out to you as important such breakthroughs

where a flurry of progress follows?

So the big famous one was 1920s,

the invention of quantum mechanics,

where in about five or 10 years,

lots of stuff got figured out.

That’s now quantum mechanics.

Can you mention the people involved?

Yeah, it was kind of the Schrodinger, Heisenberg,

Einstein had been a key figure, originally Planck,

then Dirac was a little bit later.

That was something that happened at that time,

that’s sort of before my time, right?

In my time was in the 1970s,

there was this sort of realization

that quantum field theory was actually going to be useful

in physics and QCD, quantum thermodynamics theory

of quarks and gluons and so on was really getting started.

And there was again, sort of big flurry of things

happened then, I happened to be a teenager at that time

and happened to be really involved in physics.

And so I got to be part of that, which was really cool.

Who were the key figures

aside from your young selves at that time?

You know, who won the Nobel Prize for QCD, okay?

People, David Gross, Frank Wilczek, you know, David Politzer.

The people who are the sort of the slightly older generation,

Dick Feynman, Murray Gellman, people like that,

who were Steve Weinberg, Gerhard Hoft, he’s younger,

he’s in the younger group actually.

But these are all, you know, characters who were involved.

I mean, it’s funny because those are all people

who are kind of in my time and I know them

and they don’t seem like sort of historical,

you know, iconic figures.

They seem more like everyday characters, so to speak.

And so it’s always, you know, when you look at history

from long afterwards, it always seems like

everything happened instantly.

And that’s usually not the case.

There was usually a long buildup,

but usually there’s, you know,

there’s some methodological thing happens

and then there’s a whole bunch of low hanging fruit

to be picked.

And that usually lasts five or 10 years.

You know, we see it today with machine learning

and, you know, deep learning neural nets and so on.

You know, methodological advance,

things actually started working in, you know, 2011, 2012

and so on.

And, you know, there’s been this sort of rapid

picking of low hanging fruit, which is probably, you know,

some significant fraction of the way done, so to speak.

Do you think there’s a key moment?

Like if I had to really introspect,

like what was the key moment

for the deep learning, quote unquote, revolution?

I mean.

It’s probably the AlexNet business.

AlexNet with ImageNet.

So is there something like that with physics

where, so deep learning neural networks

have been around for a long time.

Absolutely, since the 1940s, yeah.

There’s a bunch of little pieces that came together

and then all of a sudden everybody’s eyes lit up.

Like, wow, there’s something here.

Like even just looking at your own work,

just your thinking about the universe,

that there’s simple rules can create complexity.

You know, at which point was there a thing

where your eyes light up?

It’s like, wait a minute, there’s something here.

Is it the very first idea

or is it some moment along the line of implementations

and experiments and so on?

There’s a couple of different stages to this.

I mean, one is the think about the world computationally.

Can we use programs instead of equations

to make models of the world?

That’s something that I got interested in

in the beginning of the 1980s.

I did a bunch of computer experiments.

When I first did them, I didn’t really,

I could see some significance to them,

but it took me a few years to really say,

wow, there’s a big important phenomenon here

that lets sort of complex things arise

from very simple programs.

That kind of happened back in 1984 or so.

Then, you know, a bunch of other years go by,

then I start actually doing a lot

of much more systematic computer experiments and things

and find out that the, you know,

this phenomenon that I could only have said occurs

in one particular case

is actually something incredibly general.

And then that led me to this thing called

principle of computational equivalence.

And that was a long story.

And then, you know, as part of that process,

I was like, okay, you can make simple programs,

can make models of complicated things.

What about the whole universe?

That’s our sort of ultimate example of a complicated thing.

And so I got to thinking, you know,

could we use these ideas to study fundamental physics?

You know, I happen to know a lot about,

you know, traditional fundamental physics.

My first, you know, I had a bunch of ideas

about how to do this in the early 1990s.

I made a bunch of technical progress.

I figured out a bunch of things

I thought were pretty interesting.

You know, I wrote about them back in 2002.

With the new kind of science

in the cellular automata world.

And there’s echoes in the cellular automata world

with your new Wolfram physics project.

We’ll get to all that.

Allow me to sort of romanticize a little more

on the philosophy of science.

So Thomas Kuhn, philosopher of science,

describes that, you know, the progress in science

is made with these paradigm shifts.

And so to link on the sort of original line of discussion,

do you agree with this view

that there is revolutions in science

that just kind of flip the table?

What happens is it’s a different way

of thinking about things.

It’s a different methodology for studying things.

And that opens stuff up.

There’s this idea of,

he’s a famous biographer,

but I think it’s called the innovators.

There’s a biographer of Steve Jobs, of Albert Einstein.

He also wrote a book,

I think it’s called the innovators,

where he discusses how a lot of the innovations

in the history of computing has been done by groups.

There’s a complicated group dynamic going on,

but there’s also a romanticized notion

that the individual is at the core of the revolution.

Like where does your sense fall?

Is ultimately like one person responsible

for these revolutions that creates the spark

or one or two, whatever,

or is it just the big mush and mess and chaos

of people interacting, of personalities interacting?

I think it ends up being like many things,

there’s leadership and there ends up being,

it’s a lot easier for one person to have a crisp new idea

than it is for a big committee to have a crisp new idea.

And I think, but I think it can happen

that you have a great idea,

but the world isn’t ready for it.

And you can, I mean, this has happened to me plenty, right?

It’s, you have an idea, it’s actually a pretty good idea,

but things aren’t ready,

either you’re not really ready for it,

or the ambient world isn’t ready for it.

And it’s hard to get the thing to get traction.

It’s kind of interesting.

I mean, when I look at a new kind of science,

you’re now living inside the history,

so you can’t tell the story of these decades,

but it seems like the new kind of science

has not had the revolutionary impact

I would think it might.

Like, it feels like at some point, of course it might be,

but it feels at some point people will return to that book

and say, that was something special here.

This was incredible.

What happened?

Or do you think that’s already happened?

Oh, yeah, it’s happened, except that people aren’t,

the sort of the heroism of it may not be there,

but what’s happened is for 300 years,

people basically said,

if you want to make a model of things in the world,

mathematical equations are the best place to go.

Last 15 years, doesn’t happen.

New models that get made of things

most often are made with programs, not with equations.

Now, was that sort of going to happen anyway?

Was that a consequence of my particular work

and my particular book?

It’s hard to know for sure.

I mean, I am always amazed at the amounts of feedback

that I get from people where they say,

oh, by the way, I started doing this whole line of research

because I read your book, blah, blah, blah, blah, blah.

It’s like, well, can you tell that

from the academic literature?

Was there a chain of academic references?

Probably not.

One of the interesting side effects of publishing

in the way you did this tome

is it serves as an education tool and an inspiration

to hundreds of thousands, millions of people,

but because it’s not a single,

it’s not a chain of papers with spiffy titles,

it doesn’t create a splash of citations.

It’s had plenty of citations, but it’s, you know,

I think that people think of it as probably more,

you know, conceptual inspiration than kind of a,

you know, this is a line from here to here to here

in our particular field.

I think that the thing which I am disappointed by

and which will eventually happen

is this kind of study of the sort of pure computationalism,

this kind of study of the abstract behavior

of the computational universe.

That should be a big thing that lots of people do.

You mean in mathematics purely, almost like.

It’s like pure mathematics, but it isn’t mathematics.

But it isn’t, it isn’t.

It’s a new kind of mathematics.

Is it a new title of the book?

Yeah, right.

That’s why the book is called that.

Right, that’s not coincidental.

Yeah.

It’s interesting that I haven’t seen

really rigorous investigation

by thousands of people of this idea.

I mean, you look at your competition around rule 30.

I mean, that’s fascinating.

If you can say something.

Right.

Is there some aspect of this thing that could be predicted?

That’s the fundamental question of science.

That’s the core.

Well, that has been a question of science.

I think that is some people’s view of what science is about

and it’s not clear that’s the right view.

In fact, as we live through this pandemic

full of predictions and so on,

it’s an interesting moment to be pondering

what science’s actual role in those kinds of things is.

Or you think it’s possible that in science,

clean, beautiful, simple prediction

may not even be possible in real systems.

That’s the open question.

I don’t think it’s open.

I think that question is answered and the answer is no.

Well, no, no.

The answer could be just humans are not smart enough yet.

Like we don’t have the tools yet.

No, that’s the whole point.

I mean, that’s sort of the big discovery

of this principle of computational equivalence of mine.

And this is something which is kind of a follow on

to Gödel’s theorem, to Turing’s work

on the halting problem, all these kinds of things.

That there is this fundamental limitation

built into science,

this idea of computational irreducibility

that says that even though you may know the rules

by which something operates,

that does not mean that you can readily sort of

be smarter than it and jump ahead

and figure out what it’s going to do.

Yes, but do you think there’s a hope

for pockets of computational reducibility?

Computational reducibility.

And then a set of tools and mathematics

that help you discover such pockets.

That’s where we live is in the pockets of reducibility.

That’s why, and this is one of the things

that sort of come out of this physics project

and actually something that, again,

I should have realized many years ago, but didn’t,

is it could very well be that everything about the world

is computationally reducible and completely unpredictable.

But in our experience of the world,

there is at least some amount of prediction we can make.

And that’s because we have sort of chosen a slice of,

probably talk about this in much more detail,

but I mean, we’ve kind of chosen a slice

of how to think about the universe

in which we can kind of sample

a certain amount of computational reducibility.

And that’s sort of where we exist.

And it may not be the whole story of how the universe is,

but it is the part of the universe that we care about

and we sort of operate in.

And that’s, you know, in science,

that’s been sort of a very special case of that.

That is science has chosen to talk a lot about places

where there is this computational reducibility

that it can find, you know,

the motion of the planets can be more or less predicted.

You know, something about the weather

is much harder to predict.

Something about, you know, other kinds of things

that are much harder to predict.

And it’s, these are, but science has tended to,

you know, concentrate itself on places

where its methods have allowed successful prediction.

So you think rule 30, if we could linger on it,

because it’s just such a beautiful, simple formulation

of the essential concept underlying

all the things we’re talking about.

Do you think there’s pockets of reducibility

inside rule 30?

Yes, that is the question of how big are they?

What will they allow you to say?

And so on.

And that’s, and figuring out where those pockets are,

I mean, in a sense, that’s the, that’s sort of a,

you know, that is an essential thing

that one would like to do in science.

But it’s also, the important thing to realize

that has not been, you know, is that science,

if you just pick an arbitrary thing,

you say, what’s the answer to this question?

That question may not be one

that has a computationally reducible answer.

That question, if you choose, you know,

if you walk along the series of questions

and you’ve got one that’s reducible

and you get to another one that’s nearby

and it’s reducible too,

if you stick to that kind of stick to the land,

so to speak, then you can go down this chain

of sort of reducible, answerable things.

But if you just say, I’m just pick a question at random,

I’m gonna have my computer pick a question at random.

Most likely it’s gonna be reducible.

Most likely it will be reducible.

And what we’re thrown in the world, so to speak,

we, you know, when we engineer things,

we tend to engineer things to sort of keep

in the zone of reducibility.

When we’re throwing things by the natural world,

for example, not at all certain

that we will be kept in this kind of zone of reducibility.

Can we talk about this pandemic then?

Sure.

For a second, is a, so how do we,

there’s obviously huge amount of economic pain

that people are feeling.

There’s a huge incentive and medical pain,

health, just all kind of psychological.

There’s a huge incentive to figure this out,

to walk along the trajectory of reducible, of reducibility.

There’s a lot of disparate data.

You know, people understand generally how viruses spread,

but it’s very complicated

because there’s a lot of uncertainty.

There’s a, there could be a lot of variability also,

like so many, obviously a nearly infinite number

of variables that represent human interaction.

And so you have to figure out,

from the perspective of reducibility,

figure out which variables are really important

in this kind of, from an epidemiological perspective.

So why aren’t we, you kind of said

that we’re clearly failing.

Well, I think it’s a complicated thing.

So, I mean, you know, when this pandemic started up,

you know, I happened to be in the middle

of being about to release this whole physics project thing,

but I thought, you know.

The timing is just cosmically absurd.

A little bit bizarre, but you know,

but I thought, you know,

I should do the public service thing of, you know,

trying to understand what I could about the pandemic.

And, you know, we’d been curating data about it

and all that kind of thing.

But, you know, so I started looking at the data

and started looking at modeling

and I decided it’s just really hard.

You need to know a lot of stuff that we don’t know

about human interactions.

It’s actually clear now that there’s a lot of stuff

we didn’t know about viruses

and about the way immunity works and so on.

And it’s, you know, I think what will come out in the end

is there’s a certain amount of what happens

that we just kind of have to trace each step

and see what happens.

There’s a certain amount of stuff

where there’s going to be a big narrative

about this happened because, you know, of T cell immunity.

This could happen because there’s this whole giant

sort of field of asymptomatic viral stuff out there.

You know, there will be a narrative

and that narrative, whenever there’s a narrative,

that’s kind of a sign of reducibility.

But when you just say,

let’s from first principles figure out what’s going on,

then you can potentially be stuck

in this kind of a mess of irreducibility

where you just have to simulate each step

and you can’t do that unless you know details about,

you know, human interaction networks

and so on and so on and so on.

The thing that has been very sort of frustrating to see

is the mismatch between people’s expectations

about what science can deliver

and what science can actually deliver, so to speak.

Because people have this idea that, you know, it’s science.

So there must be a definite answer

and we must be able to know that answer.

And, you know, this is, it is both, you know,

when you’ve, after you’ve played around

with sort of little programs in the computational universe,

you don’t have that intuition anymore.

You know, it’s, I always, I’m always fond of saying,

you know, the computational animals

are always smarter than you are.

That is, you know, you look at one of these things

and it’s like, it can’t possibly do such and such a thing.

Then you run it and it’s like, wait a minute,

it’s doing that thing.

How does that work?

Okay, now I can go back and understand it.

But that’s the brave thing about science

is that in the chaos of the irreducible universe,

we nevertheless persist to find those pockets.

That’s kind of the whole point.

That’s like, you say that the limits of science,

but that, you know, yes, it’s highly limited,

but there’s a hope there.

And like, there’s so many questions I want to ask here.

So one, you said narrative, which is really interesting.

So obviously from a, at every level of society,

you look at Twitter, everybody’s constructing narratives

about the pandemic, about not just the pandemic,

but all the cultural tension that we’re going through.

So there’s narratives,

but they’re not necessarily connected

to the underlying reality of these systems.

So our human narratives, I don’t even know if they’re,

I don’t like those pockets of reducibility

because we’re, it’s like constructing things

that are not actually representative of reality,

and thereby not giving us like good solutions

to how to predict the system.

Look, it gets complicated because, you know,

people want to say, explain the pandemic to me,

explain what’s going to happen.

In the future.

Yes, but also, can you explain it?

Is there a story to tell?

What already happened in the past?

Yeah, or what’s going to happen,

but I mean, you know, it’s similar to sort of

explaining things in AI or in any computational system.

It’s like, you know, explain what happened.

Well, it could just be this happened

because of this detail and this detail and this detail,

and a million details,

and there isn’t a big story to tell.

There’s no kind of big arc of the story that says,

oh, it’s because, you know, there’s a viral field

that has these properties

and people start showing symptoms.

You know, when the seasons change,

people will show symptoms

and people don’t even understand, you know,

seasonal variation of flu, for example.

It’s something where, you know,

there could be a big story,

or it could be just a zillion little details that mount up.

See, but, okay, let’s pretend that this pandemic,

like the coronavirus, resembles something

like the 1D rule 30 cellular automata, okay?

So, I mean, that’s how epidemiologists model virus spread.

Indeed, yes.

They sometimes use cellular automata, yes.

Yeah, and okay, so you could say it’s simplistic,

but okay, let’s say it’s representative

of actually what happens.

You know, the dynamic of,

you have a graph,

it probably is closer to the hypergraph model.

It is, yes.

It’s actually, that’s another funny thing.

As we were getting ready to release this physics project,

we realized that a bunch of things we’d worked out

about foliations of causal graphs and things

were directly relevant to thinking about contact tracing.

Yeah, exactly.

And interactions with cell phones and so on,

which is really weird.

But like, it just feels like,

it feels like we should be able to get

some beautiful core insight about the spread

of this particular virus

on the hypergraph of human civilization, right?

I tried, I didn’t manage to figure it out.

But you’re one person.

Yeah, but I mean, I think actually it’s a funny thing

because it turns out the main model,

you know, this SIR model,

I only realized recently was invented by the grandfather

of a good friend of mine from high school.

So that was just a, you know, it’s a weird thing, right?

The question is, you know, okay, so you know,

on this graph of how humans are connected,

you know something about what happens

if this happens and that happens.

That graph is made in complicated ways

that depends on all sorts of issues

that where we don’t have the data

about how human society works well enough

to be able to make that graph.

There’s actually, one of my kids did a study

of sort of what happens on different kinds of graphs

and how robust are the results, okay?

His basic answer is there are a few general results

that you can get that are quite robust.

Like, you know, a small number of big gatherings

is worse than a large number of small gatherings, okay?

That’s quite robust.

But when you ask more detailed questions,

it seemed like it just depends.

It depends on details.

In other words, it’s kind of telling you in that case,

you know, the irreducibility matters, so to speak.

It’s not, there’s not gonna be this kind of one

sort of master theorem that says,

and therefore this is how things are gonna work.

Yeah, but there’s a certain kind of,

from a graph perspective,

the certain kind of dynamic to human interaction.

So like large groups and small groups,

I think it matters who the groups are.

For example, you could imagine large,

depends how you define large,

but you can imagine groups of 30 people,

as long as they are cliques or whatever.

Right.

As long as the outgoing degree of that graph is small

or something like that,

like you can imagine some beautiful underlying rule

of human dynamic interaction where I can still be happy,

where I can have a conversation with you

and a bunch of other people that mean a lot to me in my life

and then stay away from the bigger, I don’t know,

not going to a Miley Cyrus concert or something like that

and figuring out mathematically some nice.

See, this is an interesting thing.

So I mean, this is the question of what you’re describing

is kind of the problem of the many situations

where you would like to get away

from computational irreducibility.

A classic one in physics is thermodynamics.

The second law of thermodynamics,

the law that says entropy tends to increase things

that start orderly tend to get more disordered,

or which is also the thing that says,

given that you have a bunch of heat,

it’s hard, heat is the microscopic motion of molecules,

it’s hard to turn that heat into systematic mechanical work.

It’s hard to just take something being hot

and turn that into, oh, all the atoms are gonna line up

in the bar of metal and the piece of metal

is gonna shoot in some direction.

That’s essentially the same problem

as how do you go from this computationally irreducible

mess of things happening

and get something you want out of it.

It’s kind of mining, you’re kind of,

now, actually I’ve understood in recent years

that the story of thermodynamics

is actually precisely a story of computational irreducibility,

but it is a, it is already an analogy.

You can kind of see that as can you take the,

what you’re asking to do there

is you’re asking to go from the kind of,

the mess of all these complicated human interactions

and all this kind of computational processes going on

and you say, I want to achieve

this particular thing out of it.

I want to kind of extract from the heat of what’s happening.

I want to kind of extract this useful piece

of sort of mechanical work that I find helpful.

I mean.

Do you have a hope for the pandemic?

So we’ll talk about physics,

but for the pandemic, can that be extracted?

Do you think?

What’s your intuition?

The good news is the curves basically,

for reasons we don’t understand,

the curves, the clearly measurable mortality curves

and so on for the Northern Hemisphere have gone down.

Yeah, but the bad news is that it could be a lot worse

for future viruses.

And what this pandemic revealed is we’re highly unprepared

for the discovery of the pockets of reducibility

within a pandemic that’s much more dangerous.

Well, my guess is the specific risk of viral pandemics,

you know, that the pure virology

and immunology of the thing,

this will cause that to advance to the point

where this particular risk

is probably considerably mitigated.

But is the structure of modern society robust

to all kinds of risks?

Well, the answer is clearly no.

And it’s surprising to me the extent to which people,

as I say, it’s kind of scary actually

how much people believe in science.

That is people say, oh, you know,

because the science says this, that and the other,

we’ll do this and this and this,

even though from a sort of common sense point of view,

it’s a little bit crazy and people are not prepared

and it doesn’t really work in society

as it is for people to say,

well, actually we don’t really know how the science works.

People say, well, tell us what to do.

Yeah, because then, yeah, what’s the alternative?

For the masses, it’s difficult to sit,

it’s difficult to meditate on computational reducibility.

It’s difficult to sit,

it’s difficult to enjoy a good dinner meal

while knowing that you know nothing about the world.

Well, I think this is a place where, you know,

this is what politicians and political leaders do

for a living, so to speak,

is you’ve got to make some decision about what to do.

And it’s…

Tell some narrative that while amidst the mystery

and knowing not much about the past or the future,

still telling a narrative that somehow gives people hope

that we know what the heck we’re doing.

Yeah, and get society through the issue.

You know, even though, you know,

the idea that we’re just gonna, you know,

sort of be able to get the definitive answer from science

and it’s gonna tell us exactly what to do.

Unfortunately, you know, it’s interesting

because let me point out that if that was possible,

if science could always tell us what to do,

then in a sense, our, you know,

that would be a big downer for our lives.

If science could always tell us

what the answer is gonna be,

it’s like, well, you know,

it’s kind of fun to live one’s life

and just sort of see what happens.

If one could always just say,

let me check my science.

Oh, I know, you know,

the result of everything is gonna be 42.

I don’t need to live my life and do what I do.

It’s just, we already know the answer.

It’s actually good news in a sense

that there is this phenomenon

of computational irreducibility

that doesn’t allow you to just sort of jump through time

and say, this is the answer, so to speak.

And that’s, so that’s a good thing.

The bad thing is it doesn’t allow you to jump through time

and know what the answer is.

It’s scary.

Do you think we’re gonna be okay as a human civilization?

You said, we don’t know.

Absolutely.

Do you think we’ll prosper or destroy ourselves?

In general?

In general.

I’m an optimist.

No, I think that, you know,

it’ll be interesting to see, for example,

with this, you know, pandemic,

I, you know, to me, you know,

when you look at like organizations, for example,

you know, having some kind of perturbation,

some kick to the system,

usually the end result of that is actually quite good.

You know, unless it kills the system,

it’s actually quite good usually.

And I think in this case, you know, people,

I mean, my impression, you know,

it’s a little weird for me because, you know,

I’ve been a remote tech CEO for 30 years.

It doesn’t, you know, this is bizarrely, you know,

and the fact that, you know, like this coming to see you here

is the first time in six months that I’ve been like,

you know, in a building other than my house, okay?

So, you know, I’m a kind of ridiculous outlier

in these kinds of things.

But overall, your sense is when you shake up the system

and throw in chaos that you challenge the system,

we humans emerge better.

Seems to be that way.

Who’s to know?

I think that, you know, people, you know,

my sort of vague impression is that people are sort of,

you know, oh, what’s actually important?

You know, what is worth caring about and so on?

And that seems to be something that perhaps is more,

you know, emergent in this kind of situation.

It’s so fascinating that on the individual level,

we have our own complex cognition.

We have consciousness, we have intelligence,

we’re trying to figure out little puzzles.

And then that somehow creates this graph

of collective intelligence.

Well, we figure out, and then you throw in these viruses

of which there’s millions different, you know,

there’s entire taxonomy and the viruses are thrown

into the system of collective human intelligence.

And when little humans figure out what to do about it,

we get like, we tweet stuff about information.

There’s doctors as conspiracy theorists.

And then we play with different information.

I mean, the whole of it is fascinating.

I am like you also very optimistic,

but you said the computational reducibility.

There’s always a fear of the darkness

of the uncertainty before us.

Yeah, I know. And it’s scary.

I mean, the thing is, if you knew everything,

it will be boring.

And it would be, and then, and worse than boring,

so to speak.

It would reveal the pointlessness, so to speak.

And in a sense, the fact that there is

this computational irreducibility,

it’s like as we live our lives, so to speak,

something is being achieved.

We’re computing what our lives, you know,

what happens in our lives.

That’s funny.

So the computational reducibility is kind of like,

it gives the meaning to life.

It is the meaning of life.

Computational reducibility is the meaning of life.

There you go.

It gives it meaning, yes.

I mean, it’s what causes it to not be something

where you can just say, you know,

you went through all those steps to live your life,

but we already knew what the answer was.

Hold on one second.

I’m going to use my handy Wolfram Alpha sunburn

computation thing, so long as I can get network here.

There we go.

Oh, actually, you know what?

It says sunburn unlikely.

This is a QA moment.

This is a good moment.

Okay, well, let me just check what it thinks.

See why it thinks that.

It doesn’t seem like my intuition.

This is one of these cases where we can,

the question is, do we trust the science

or do we use common sense?

The UV thing is cool.

Yeah, yeah, well, we’ll see.

This is a QA moment, as I say.

It’s, do we trust the product?

Yes, we trust the product, so.

And then there’ll be a data point either way.

If I’m desperately sunburned,

I will send in an angry feedback.

Because we mentioned the concept so much

and a lot of people know it,

but can you say what computational reducibility is?

Yeah, right.

The question is, if you think about things

that happen as being computations,

you think about some process in physics,

something that you compute in mathematics, whatever else,

it’s a computation in the sense it has definite rules.

You follow those rules.

You follow them many steps and you get some result.

So then the issue is,

if you look at all these different kinds of computations

that can happen,

whether they’re computations

that are happening in the natural world,

whether they’re happening in our brains,

whether they’re happening in our mathematics,

whatever else,

the big question is, how do these computations compare?

Is, are there dumb computations and smart computations

or are they somehow all equivalent?

And the thing that I kind of was sort of surprised to realize

from a bunch of experiments that I did in the early nineties

and now we have tons more evidence for it,

this thing I call the principle of computational equivalence,

which basically says, when one of these computations,

one of these processes that follows rules,

doesn’t seem like it’s doing something obviously simple,

then it has reached the sort of equivalent level

of computational sophistication of everything.

So what does that mean?

That means that, you might say, gosh,

I’m studying this little tiny program on my computer.

I’m studying this little thing in nature,

but I have my brain

and my brain is surely much smarter than that thing.

I’m gonna be able to systematically outrun

the computation that it does

because I have a more sophisticated computation

that I can do.

But what the principle of computational equivalence says

is that doesn’t work.

Our brains are doing computations

that are exactly equivalent to the kinds of computations

that are being done in all these other sorts of systems.

And so what consequences does that have?

Well, it means that we can’t systematically

outrun these systems.

These systems are computationally irreducible

in the sense that there’s no sort of shortcut

that we can make that jumps to the answer.

Now the general case.

Right, right.

But the, so what has happened,

what science has become used to doing

is using the little sort of pockets

of computational reducibility,

which by the way are an inevitable consequence

of computational irreducibility,

that there have to be these pockets

scattered around of computational reducibility

to be able to find those particular cases

where you can jump ahead.

I mean, one thing sort of a little bit

of a parable type thing that I think is fun to tell.

If you look at ancient Babylon,

they were trying to predict three kinds of things.

They tried to predict where the planets would be,

what the weather would be like,

and who would win or lose a certain battle.

And they had no idea which of these things

would be more predictable than the other.

That’s funny.

And it turns out where the planets are

is a piece of computational reducibility

that 300 years ago or so we pretty much cracked.

I mean, it’s been technically difficult

to get all the details right,

but it’s basically, we got that.

Who’s gonna win or lose the battle?

No, we didn’t crack that one.

That one, that one, right.

Game theorists are trying.

Yes. And then the weather.

It’s kind of halfway on that one.

Halfway?

Yeah, I think we’re doing okay on that one.

Long term climate, different story.

But the weather, we’re much closer on that.

But do you think eventually we’ll figure out the weather?

So do you think eventually most think

we’ll figure out the local pockets in everything,

essentially the local pockets of reducibility?

No, I think that it’s an interesting question,

but I think that there is an infinite collection

of these local pockets.

We’ll never run out of local pockets.

And by the way, those local pockets

are where we build engineering, for example.

That’s how we, if we want to have a predictable life,

so to speak, then we have to build

in these sort of pockets of reducibility.

Otherwise, if we were sort of existing

in this kind of irreducible world,

we’d never be able to have definite things

to know what’s gonna happen.

I have to say, I think one of the features,

when we look at sort of today from the future, so to speak,

I suspect one of the things where people will say

I can’t believe they didn’t see that

is stuff to do with the following kind of thing.

So if we describe, oh, I don’t know,

something like heat, for instance,

we say, oh, the air in here, it’s this temperature,

this pressure, that’s as much as we can say.

Otherwise, just a bunch of random molecules bouncing around.

People will say, I just can’t believe they didn’t realize

that there was all this detail

and how all these molecules were bouncing around

and they could make use of that.

And actually, I realized there’s a thing

I realized last week, actually,

was a thing that people say, one of the scenarios

for the very long term history of our universe

is a so called heat death of the universe,

where basically everything just becomes

thermodynamically boring.

Everything’s just this big kind of gas

and thermal equilibrium.

People say, that’s a really bad outcome.

But actually, it’s not a really bad outcome.

It’s an outcome where there’s all this computation going on

and all those individual gas molecules

are all bouncing around in very complicated ways

doing this very elaborate computation.

It just happens to be a computation that right now,

we haven’t found ways to understand.

We haven’t found ways, our brains haven’t,

and our mathematics and our science and so on,

haven’t found ways to tell an interesting story about that.

It just looks boring to us.

So you’re saying there’s a hopeful view

of the heat death, quote unquote, of the universe

where there’s actual beautiful complexity going on.

Similar to the kind of complexity we think of

that creates rich experience in human life and life on Earth.

So those little molecules interacting complex ways,

that could be intelligence in that, there could be.

Absolutely.

I mean, this is what you learn from this principle.

Wow, that’s a hopeful message.

Right.

I mean, this is what you kind of learn

from this principle of computational equivalence.

You learn it’s both a message of sort of hope

and a message of kind of, you know,

you’re not as special as you think you are, so to speak.

I mean, because, you know, we imagine that

with sort of all the things we do with human intelligence

and all that kind of thing,

and all of the stuff we’ve constructed in science,

it’s like, we’re very special.

But actually it turns out, well, no, we’re not.

We’re just doing computations

like things in nature do computations,

like those gas molecules do computations,

like the weather does computations.

The only thing about the computations that we do

that’s really special is that we understand

what they are, so to speak.

In other words, we have a, you know,

to us they’re special because kind of,

they’re connected to our purposes,

our ways of thinking about things and so on.

And that’s some, but so.

That’s very human centric.

That’s, we’re just attached to this kind of thing.

So let’s talk a little bit of physics.

Maybe let’s ask the biggest question.

What is a theory of everything in general?

What does that mean?

Yeah, so I mean, the question is,

can we kind of reduce what has been physics

as a something where we have to sort of pick away and say,

do we roughly know how the world works

to something where we have a complete formal theory

where we say, if we were to run this program

for long enough, we would reproduce everything,

you know, down to the fact that we’re having

this conversation at this moment,

et cetera, et cetera, et cetera.

Any physical phenomena, any phenomena in this world?

Any phenomenon in the universe.

But the, you know, because of computational irreducibility,

it’s not, you know, that’s not something where you say,

okay, you’ve got the fundamental theory of everything.

Then, you know, tell me whether, you know,

lions are gonna eat tigers or something.

You know, that’s a, no, you have to run this thing

for, you know, 10 to the 500 steps or something

to know something like that, okay?

So at some moment, potentially, you say,

this is a rule and run this rule enough times

and you will get the whole universe, right?

That’s what it means to kind of have

a fundamental theory of physics as far as I’m concerned

is you’ve got this rule.

It’s potentially quite simple.

We don’t know for sure it’s simple,

but we have various reasons to believe it might be simple.

And then you say, okay, I’m showing you this rule.

You just run it only 10 to the 500 times

and you’ll get everything.

In other words, you’ve kind of reduced the problem

of physics to a problem of mathematics, so to speak.

It’s like, it’s as if, you know, you’d like,

you generate the digits of pi.

There’s a definite procedure.

You just generate them and it’d be the same thing

if you have a fundamental theory of physics

of the kind that I’m imagining, you know,

you get this rule and you just run it out

and you get everything that happens in the universe.

So a theory of everything is a mathematical framework

within which you can explain everything that happens

in the universe, it’s kind of in a unified way.

It’s not, there’s a bunch of disparate modules of,

does it feel like if you create a rule

and we’ll talk about the Wolfram physics model,

which is fascinating, but if you have a simple set

of rules with a data structure, like a hypergraph,

does that feel like a satisfying theory of everything?

Because then you really run up against the irreducibility,

computational irreducibility.

Right, so that’s a really interesting question.

So I, you know, what I thought was gonna happen

is I thought we, you know, I thought we had a pretty good,

I had a pretty good idea for what the structure

of this sort of theory that sort of underneath space

and time and so on might be like.

And I thought, gosh, you know, in my lifetime,

so to speak, we might be able to figure out what happens

in the first 10 to the minus 100 seconds of the universe.

And that would be cool, but it’s pretty far away

from anything that we can see today.

And it will be hard to test whether that’s right

and so on and so on and so on.

To my huge surprise, although it should have been obvious

and it’s embarrassing that it wasn’t obvious to me,

but to my huge surprise,

we managed to get unbelievably much further than that.

And basically what happened is that it turns out

that even though there’s this kind of bed

of computational irreducibility,

that sort of these, all these simple rules run into,

there are certain pieces of computational reducibility

that quite generically occur

for large classes of these rules.

And, and this is the really exciting thing

as far as I’m concerned,

the big pieces of computational reducibility

are basically the pillars of 20th century physics.

That’s the amazing thing,

that general relativity and quantum field theory

is sort of the pillars of 20th century physics

turn out to be precisely the stuff you can say.

There’s a lot you can’t say,

there’s a lot that’s kind of at this irreducible level

where you kind of don’t know what’s going to happen,

you have to run it, you know,

you can’t run it within our universe,

et cetera, et cetera, et cetera, et cetera.

But the thing is there are things you can say

and the things you can say turn out to be very beautifully

exactly the structure that was found

in 20th century physics,

namely general relativity and quantum mechanics.

And general relativity and quantum mechanics

are these pockets of reducibility that we think of as,

that 20th century physics

is essentially pockets of reducibility.

And then it is incredibly surprising

that any kind of model that’s generative

from simple rules would have such pockets.

Yeah, well, I think what’s surprising

is we didn’t know where those things came from.

It’s like general relativity,

it’s a very nice mathematically elegant theory.

Why is it true?

You know, quantum mechanics, why is it true?

What we realized is that from this,

that these theories are generic

to a huge class of systems

that have these particular

very unstructured underlying rules.

And that’s the thing that is sort of remarkable

and that’s the thing to me

that’s just, it’s really beautiful.

I mean, it’s, and the thing that’s even more beautiful

is that it turns out that, you know,

people have been struggling for a long time.

You know, how does general relativity theory of gravity

relate to quantum mechanics?

They seem to have all kinds of incompatibilities.

It turns out what we realized is

at some level they are the same theory.

And that’s just, it’s just great as far as I’m concerned.

So maybe like taking a little step back

from your perspective, not from the low,

not from the beautiful hypergraph,

well, from physics model perspective,

but from the perspective of 20th century physics,

what is general relativity?

What is quantum mechanics?

How do you think about these two theories

from the context of the theory of everything?

Like just even definition.

Yeah, yeah, yeah, right.

So I mean, you know, a little bit of history of physics,

right?

So, I mean the, you know, okay,

very, very quick history of this, right?

So, I mean, you know, physics, you know,

in ancient Greek times, people basically said,

we can just figure out how the world works.

As you know, we’re philosophers,

we’re gonna figure out how the world works.

You know, some philosophers thought there were atoms.

Some philosophers thought there were,

you know, continuous flows of things.

People had different ideas about how the world works.

And they tried to just say,

we’re gonna construct this idea of how the world works.

They didn’t really have sort of notions

of doing experiments and so on quite the same way

as developed later.

So that was sort of an early tradition

for thinking about sort of models of the world.

Then by the time of 1600s, time of Galileo and then Newton,

sort of the big idea there was, you know,

title of Newton’s book, you know, Principia Mathematica,

mathematical principles of natural philosophy.

We can use mathematics to understand natural philosophy,

to understand things about the way the world works.

And so that then led to this kind of idea that, you know,

we can write down a mathematical equation

and have that represent how the world works.

So Newton’s one of his most famous ones

is his universal law of gravity,

inverse square law of gravity

that allowed him to compute all sorts of features

of the planets and so on.

Although some of them he got wrong

and it took another hundred years

for people to actually be able to do the math

to the level that was needed.

But so that had been this sort of tradition

was we write down these mathematical equations.

We don’t really know where these equations come from.

We write them down.

Then we figure out, we work out the consequences

and we say, yes, that agrees with what we actually observe

in astronomy or something like this.

So that tradition continued.

And then the first of these two

sort of great 20th century innovations was,

well, the history is actually a little bit more complicated,

but let’s say that there were two,

quantum mechanics and general relativity.

Quantum mechanics kind of 1900

was kind of the very early stuff done by Planck

that led to the idea of photons, particles of light.

But let’s take general relativity first.

One feature of the story is that special relativity

thing Einstein invented in 1905

was something which surprisingly

was a kind of logically invented theory.

It was not a theory where it was something where

given these ideas that were sort of axiomatically

thought to be true about the world,

it followed that such and such a thing would be the case.

It was a little bit different

from the kind of methodological structure

of some existing theories in the more recent times,

where it’s just been, we write down an equation

and we find out that it works.

So what happened there.

So there’s some reasoning about the light.

The basic idea was the speed of light

appears to be constant.

Even if you’re traveling very fast,

you shine a flashlight, the light will come out.

Even if you’re going at half the speed of light,

the light doesn’t come out of your flashlight

at one and a half times the speed of light.

It’s still just the speed of light.

And to make that work,

you have to change your view of how space and time work

to be able to account for the fact

that when you’re going faster,

it appears that length is foreshortened

and time is dilated and things like this.

And that’s special relativity.

That’s special relativity.

So then Einstein went on with sort of

vaguely similar kinds of thinking.

In 1915, invented general relativity,

which is the theory of gravity.

And the basic point of general relativity

is it’s a theory that says,

when there is mass in space, space is curved.

And what does that mean?

Usually you think of what’s the shortest distance

between two points.

Like ordinarily on a plane in space, it’s a straight line.

Photons, light goes in straight lines.

Well, then the question is,

is if you have a curved surface,

a straight line is no longer straight.

On the surface of the earth,

the shortest distance between two points is a great circle.

It’s a circle.

So, you know, Einstein’s observation was

maybe the physical structure of space

is such that space is curved.

So the shortest distance between two points,

the path, the straight line in quotes,

won’t be straight anymore.

And in particular, if a photon is, you know,

traveling near the sun or something,

or if a particle is going,

something is traveling near the sun,

maybe the shortest path will be one

that is something which looks curved to us

because it seems curved to us

because space has been deformed by the presence of mass

associated with that massive object.

So the kind of the idea there is,

think of the structure of space

as being a dynamical changing kind of thing.

But then what Einstein did

was he wrote down these differential equations

that basically represented the curvature of space

and its response to the presence of mass and energy.

And that ultimately is connected to the force of gravity,

which is one of the forces that seems to,

based on its strength,

operate on a different scale than some of the other forces.

So it operates in a scale that’s very large.

What happens there is just this curvature of space,

which causes, you know, the paths of objects to be deflected.

That’s what gravity does.

It causes the paths of objects to be deflected.

And this is an explanation for gravity, so to speak.

And the surprise is that from 1915 until today,

everything that we’ve measured about gravity

precisely agrees with general relativity.

And that, you know, it wasn’t clear black holes

were sort of a predict,

well, actually the expansion of the universe

was an early potential prediction,

although Einstein tried to sort of patch up his equations

to make it not cause the universe to expand,

because it was kind of so obvious

the universe wasn’t expanding.

And, you know, it turns out it was expanding

and he should have just trusted the equations.

And that’s a lesson for those of us

interested in making fundamental theories of physics

is you should trust your theory and not try and patch it

because of something that you think might be the case

that might turn out not to be the case.

Even if the theory says something crazy is happening.

Yeah, right.

Like the universe is expanding.

Like the universe is expanding, right, which is,

but, you know, then it took until the 1940s,

probably even really until the 1960s,

until people understood that black holes

were a consequence of general relativity and so on.

But that’s, you know, the big surprise has been

that so far this theory of gravity has perfectly agreed

with, you know, these collisions of black holes

seen by their gravitational waves, you know,

it all just works.

So that’s been kind of one pillar of the story of physics

it’s mathematically complicated to work out

the consequences of general relativity,

but it’s not, there’s no, I mean,

and some things are kind of squiggly and complicated.

Like people believe, you know, energy is conserved.

Okay, well, energy conservation doesn’t really work

in general activity in the same way as it ordinarily does.

And it’s all a big mathematical story

of how you actually nail down something that is definitive

that you can talk about it and not specific to the,

you know, reference frames you’re operating in

and so on and so on and so on.

But fundamentally, general relativity is a straight shot

in the sense that you have this theory,

you work out its consequences.

And that theory is useful in terms of basic science

and trying to understand the way black holes work,

the way the creation of galaxies work,

sort of all of these kinds of cosmological things,

understanding what happened, like you said, at the Big Bang.

Yeah. Like all those kinds of,

well, no, not at the Big Bang actually, right?

But the…

Well, features of the expansion of the universe, yes.

I mean, and there are lots of details

where we don’t quite know how it’s working, you know,

is there, you know, where’s the dark matter,

is there dark energy, you know, et cetera, et cetera, et cetera.

But fundamentally, the, you know,

the testable features of general relativity,

it all works very beautifully.

And it’s in a sense, it is mathematically sophisticated,

but it is not conceptually hard to understand in some sense.

Okay. So that’s general relativity.

And what’s its friendly neighbor, like you said,

there’s two theories, quantum mechanics.

Right. So quantum mechanics,

the sort of the way that that originated was,

one question was, is the world continuous or is it discrete?

You know, in ancient Greek times,

people have been debating this.

People debated it, you know, throughout history.

Is light made of waves?

Is it continuous? Is it discrete?

Is it made of particles, corpuscles, whatever.

You know, what had become clear in the 1800s is that atoms,

that, you know, materials are made of discrete atoms.

You know, when you take some water,

the water is not a continuous fluid,

even though it seems like a continuous fluid

to us at our scale.

But if you say, let’s look at it,

smaller and smaller and smaller and smaller scale,

eventually you get down to these, you know,

these molecules and then atoms.

It’s made of discrete things.

The question is sort of how important is this discreteness?

Just what’s discrete, what’s not discrete?

Is energy discrete?

Is, you know, what’s discrete, what’s not?

And so.

Does it have mass?

Those kinds of questions.

Yeah, yeah, right.

Well, there’s a question, I mean, for example,

is mass discrete is an interesting question,

which is now something we can address.

But, you know, what happened in the coming up to the 1920s,

there was this kind of mathematical theory developed

that could explain certain kinds of discreteness

in particularly in features of atoms and so on.

And, you know, what developed was this mathematical theory

that was the theory of quantum mechanics,

theory of wave functions, Schrodinger’s equation,

things like this.

That’s a mathematical theory that allows you to calculate

lots of features of the microscopic world,

lots of things about how atoms work,

et cetera, et cetera, et cetera.

Now, the calculations all work just great.

The question of what does it really mean

is a complicated question.

Now, I mean, to just explain a little bit historically,

the, you know, the early calculations of things like atoms

worked great in 1920s, 1930s and so on.

There was always a problem.

There were, in quantum field theory,

which is a theory of, in quantum mechanics,

you’re dealing with a certain number of electrons

and you fix the number of electrons.

You say, I’m dealing with a two electron thing.

In quantum field theory,

you allow for particles being created and destroyed.

So you can emit a photon that didn’t exist before.

You can absorb a photon, things like that.

That’s a more complicated,

mathematically complicated theory.

And it had all kinds of mathematical issues

and all kinds of infinities that cropped up.

And it was finally figured out more or less

how to get rid of those.

But there were only certain ways of doing the calculations

and those didn’t work for atomic nuclei among other things.

And that led to a lot of development up until the 1960s

of alternative ideas for how one could understand

what was happening in atomic nuclei, et cetera,

et cetera, et cetera.

End result, in the end,

the kind of most quotes obvious mathematical structure

of quantum field theory seems to work.

Although it’s mathematically difficult to deal with,

but you can calculate all kinds of things.

You can calculate to a dozen decimal places,

certain things, you can measure them.

It all works.

It’s all beautiful.

Now you say…

The underlying fabric is the model

of that particular theory is fields.

Like you keep saying fields.

Those are quantum fields.

Those are different from classical fields.

A field is something like you say,

like you say the temperature field in this room.

It’s like there is a value of temperature

at every point around the room.

That’s some, or you can say the wind field

would be the vector direction of the wind at every point.

It’s continuous.

Yes, and that’s a classical field.

The quantum field is a much more

mathematically elaborate kind of thing.

And I should explain that one of the pictures

of quantum mechanics that’s really important is,

in classical physics, one believes

that sort of definite things happen in the world.

You pick up a ball, you throw it,

the ball goes in a definite trajectory

that has certain equations of motion.

It goes in a parabola, whatever else.

In quantum mechanics, the picture is

definite things don’t happen.

Instead, sort of what happens is this whole

sort of structure of all many different paths being followed

and we can calculate certain aspects of what happens,

certain probabilities of different outcomes and so on.

And you say, well, what really happened?

What’s really going on?

What’s the sort of, what’s the underlying,

what’s the underlying story?

How do we turn this mathematical theory

that we can calculate things with

into something that we can really understand

and have a narrative about?

And that’s been really, really hard for quantum mechanics.

My friend, Dick Feynman, always used to say,

nobody understands quantum mechanics,

even though he’d made his whole career

out of calculating things about quantum mechanics.

And so it’s a little bit.

Nevertheless, it’s what the quantum field theory is very,

very accurate at predicting a lot of the physical phenomena.

So it works.

Yeah.

But there are things about it, it has certain,

when we apply it, the standard model of particle physics,

for example, we, which we apply to calculate

all kinds of things that works really well.

And you say, well, it has certain parameters.

It has a whole bunch of parameters actually.

You say, why is the, why does the muon particle exist?

Why is it 206 times the mass of the electron?

We don’t know, no idea.

But so the standard model of physics is one of the models

that’s very accurate for describing

three of the fundamental forces of physics.

And it’s looking at the world of the very small.

Right.

And then there’s back to the neighbor of gravity,

of general relativity.

So, and then in the context of a theory of everything,

what’s traditionally the task of the unification

of these theories?

And why is it hard?

The issue is you try to use the methods

of quantum field theory to talk about gravity

and it doesn’t work.

Just like there are photons of light.

So there are gravitons,

which are sort of the particles of gravity.

And when you try and compute sort of the properties

of the particles of gravity,

the kind of mathematical tricks that get used

in working things out in quantum field theory don’t work.

And that’s, so that’s been a sort of fundamental issue.

And when you think about black holes,

which are a place where sort of the structure of space

is, you know, has sort of rapid variation

and you get kind of quantum effects mixed in

with effects from general relativity,

things get very complicated

and there are apparent paradoxes and things like that.

And people have, you know,

there’ve been a bunch of mathematical developments

in physics over the last, I don’t know, 30 years or so,

which have kind of picked away at those kinds of issues

and got hints about how things might work.

But it hasn’t been, you know,

and the other thing to realize is,

as far as physics is concerned,

it’s just like here’s general relativity,

here’s quantum field theory, you know, be happy.

Yeah, so do you think there’s a quantization of gravity,

so quantum gravity, what do you think of efforts

that people have tried to, yeah,

what do you think in general of the efforts

of the physics community to try to unify these laws?

So I think what’s, it’s interesting.

I mean, I would have said something very different

before what’s happened with our physics project.

I mean, you know, the remarkable thing is

what we’ve been able to do is to make

from this very simple, structurally simple,

underlying set of ideas,

we’ve been able to build this, you know,

very elaborate structure that’s both very abstract

and very sort of mathematically rich.

And the big surprise, as far as I’m concerned,

is that it touches many of the ideas that people have had.

So in other words, things like string theory and so on,

twister theory, it’s like the, you know,

we might’ve thought, I had thought we’re out on a prong,

we’re building something that’s computational,

it’s completely different from what other people have done.

But actually it seems like what we’ve done

is to provide essentially the machine code that, you know,

these things are various features

of domain specific languages, so to speak,

that talk about various aspects of this machine code.

And I think this is something that to me is very exciting

because it allows one both for us to provide

sort of a new foundation for what’s been thought about there

and for all the work that’s been done in those areas

to give us, you know, more momentum

to be able to figure out what’s going on.

Now, you know, people have sort of hoped,

oh, we’re just gonna be able to get, you know,

string theory to just answer everything.

That hasn’t worked out.

And I think we now kind of can see a little bit about

just sort of how far away certain kinds of things are

from being able to explain things.

Some things, one of the big surprises to me,

actually I literally just got a message

about one aspect of this is the, you know,

it’s turning out to be easier.

I mean, this project has been so much easier

than I could ever imagine it would be.

That is, I thought we would be, you know,

just about able to understand

the first 10 to the minus 100 seconds of the universe.

And, you know, it would be a hundred years

before we get much further than that.

It’s just turned out, it actually wasn’t that hard.

I mean, we’re not finished, but, you know.

So you’re seeing echoes of all the disparate theories

of physics in this framework.

Yes, yes.

I mean, it’s a very interesting, you know,

sort of history of science like phenomenon.

I mean, the best analogy that I can see

is what happened with the early days

of computability and computation theory.

You know, Turing machines were invented in 1936.

People sort of understand computation

in terms of Turing machines,

but actually there had been preexisting theories

of computation, combinators, general recursive functions,

Lambda calculus, things like this.

But people hadn’t, those hadn’t been concrete enough

that people could really wrap their arms around them

and understand what was going on.

And I think what we’re gonna see in this case

is that a bunch of these mathematical theories,

including some very,

I mean, one of the things that’s really interesting

is one of the most abstract things

that’s come out of sort of mathematics,

higher category theory, things about infinity group voids,

things like this, which to me always just seemed

like they were floating off into the stratosphere,

ionosphere of mathematics, turn out to be things

which our sort of theory anchors down

to something fairly definite and says are super relevant

to the way that we can understand how physics works.

Give me a sec.

By the way, I just threw a hat on.

You’ve said that with this metaphor analogy

that the theory of everything is a big mountain

and you have a sense that however far we are up the mountain,

that the Wolfram physics model view of the universe

is at least the right mountain.

We’re the right mountain, yes, without question.

Which aspect of it is the right mountain?

So for example, I mean, so there’s so many aspects

to just the way of the Wolfram physics project,

the way it approaches the world that’s clean, crisp,

and unique and powerful, so there’s a discreet nature to it,

there’s a hypergraph, there’s a computational nature,

there’s a generative aspect, you start from nothing,

you generate everything, do you think the actual model

is actually a really good one,

or do you think this general principle

from simplicity generating complexity is the right,

like what aspect of the mountain is the correct?

Yeah, right, I think that the kind of the meta idea

about using simple computational systems to do things,

that’s the ultimate big paradigm

that is sort of super important.

The details of the particular model are very nice and clean

and allow one to actually understand what’s going on.

They are not unique, and in fact, we know that.

We know that there’s a very, very, very, very,

there’s a large number of different ways

to describe essentially the same thing.

I mean, I can describe things in terms of hypergraphs,

I can describe them in terms of higher category theory,

I can describe them in a bunch of different ways.

They are in some sense all the same thing,

but our sort of story about what’s going on

and the kind of cultural mathematical resonances

are a bit different.

And I think it’s perhaps worth sort of saying a little bit

about kind of the foundational ideas

of these models and things.

Great, so can you maybe, can we like rewind?

We’ve talked about it a little bit,

but can you say like what the central idea is

of the Wolfram Physics Project?

Right, so the question is we’re interested

in finding sort of simple computational rule

that describes our whole universe.

Can we just pause on that?

It’s just so beautiful, that’s such a beautiful idea

that we can generate our universe

from a data structure, a simple structure,

simple set of rules, and we can generate our entire universe.

Yes, that’s the idea. That’s awe inspiring.

Right, but so the question is how do you actualize that?

What might this rule be like?

And so one thing you quickly realize is

if you’re gonna pack everything about our universe

into this tiny rule, not much that we are familiar with

in our universe will be obvious in that rule.

So you don’t get to fit all these parameters of the universe,

all these features of, you know, this is how space works,

this is how time works, et cetera, et cetera, et cetera.

You don’t get to fit that all in.

It all has to be sort of packed in to this thing,

something much smaller, much more basic,

much lower level machine code, so to speak, than that.

And all the stuff that we’re familiar with

has to kind of emerge from the operation.

So the rule in itself,

because of the computational reducibility,

is not gonna tell you the story.

It’s not gonna give you the answer to,

it’s not gonna let you predict

what you’re gonna have for lunch tomorrow,

and it’s not going to let you predict

basically anything about your life, about the universe.

Right, and you’re not going to be able to see in that rule,

oh, there’s the three

for the number of dimensions of space and so on.

That’s not gonna be there.

Spacetime is not going to be obviously.

Right, so the question is then,

what is the universe made of?

That’s a basic question.

And we’ve had some assumptions

about what the universe is made of

for the last few thousand years

that I think in some cases just turn out not to be right.

And the most important assumption

is that space is a continuous thing.

That is that you can, if you say,

let’s pick a point in space.

We’re gonna do geometry.

We’re gonna pick a point.

We can pick a point absolutely anywhere in space.

Precise numbers we can specify of where that point is.

In fact, Euclid who kind of wrote down

the original kind of axiomatization of geometry

back in 300 BC or so,

his very first definition, he says,

a point is that which has no part.

A point is this indivisible infinitesimal thing.

Okay, so we might’ve said that about material objects.

We might’ve said that about water, for example.

We might’ve said water is a continuous thing

that we can just pick any point we want in some water,

but actually we know it isn’t true.

We know that water is made of molecules that are discrete.

And so the question, one fundamental question

is what is space made of?

And so one of the things that’s sort of a starting point

for what I’ve done is to think of space as a discrete thing,

to think of there being sort of atoms of space

just as there are atoms of material things,

although very different kinds of atoms.

And by the way, I mean, this idea,

you know, there were ancient Greek philosophers

who had this idea.

There were, you know, Einstein actually thought

this is probably how things would work out.

I mean, he said, you know, repeatedly he thought

that’s the way it would work out.

We don’t have the mathematical tools in our time,

which was 1940s, 1950s and so on to explore this.

Like the way he thought,

you mean that there is something very, very small

and discrete that’s underlying space.

Yes.

And that means that, so, you know, the mathematical theory,

mathematical theories in physics assume that space

can be described just as a continuous thing.

You can just pick coordinates

and the coordinates can have any values.

And that’s how you define space.

Space is this just sort of background sort of theater

on which the universe operates.

But can we draw a distinction between space

as a thing that could be described by three values,

coordinates, and how you’re,

are you using the word space more generally when you say?

No, I’m just talking about space

as in what we experience in the universe.

So that you think this 3D aspect of it is fundamental.

No, I don’t think that 3D is fundamental at all, actually.

I think that the thing that has been assumed

is that space is this continuous thing

where you can just describe it by,

let’s say three numbers, for instance.

But most important thing about that

is that you can describe it by precise numbers

because you can pick any point in space

and you can talk about motions,

any infinitesimal motion in space.

And that’s what continuous means.

That’s what continuous means.

That’s what, you know, Newton invented calculus

to describe these kind of continuous small variations

and so on.

That was, that’s kind of a fundamental idea

from Euclid on that’s been a fundamental idea about space.

And so.

Is that right or wrong?

It’s not right.

It’s right at the level of our experience most of the time.

It’s not right at the level of the machine code,

so to speak.

And so.

Machine code.

Yeah, of the simulation.

That’s right.

They’re the very lowest level of the fabric of the universe,

at least under the Wolfram physics model

is your senses is discrete.

Right.

So now what does that mean?

So it means what is space then?

So in models, the basic idea is you say

there are these sort of atoms of space.

They’re these points that represent,

you know, represent places in space,

but they’re just discrete points.

And the only thing we know about them

is how they’re connected to each other.

We don’t know where they are.

They don’t have coordinates.

We don’t get to say this is a position, such and such.

It’s just, here’s a big bag of points.

Like in our universe,

there might be 10 to the 100 of these points.

And all we know is this point is connected

to this other point.

So it’s like, you know,

all we have is the friend network, so to speak.

We don’t have, you know, people’s, you know,

physical addresses.

All we have is the friend network of these points.

Yeah.

The underlying nature of reality is kind of like a Facebook.

We don’t know their location, but we have the friends.

Yeah, yeah, right.

We know which point is connected to which other points.

And that’s all we know.

And so you might say, well,

how on earth can you get something

which is like our experience of, you know,

what seems like continuous space?

Well, the answer is,

by the time you have 10 to the 100 of these things,

those connections can work in such a way

that on a large scale,

it will seem to be like continuous space

in let’s say three dimensions

or some other number of dimensions

or 2.6 dimensions or whatever else.

Because they’re much, much, much, much larger.

So like the number of relationships here we’re talking about

is just a humongous amount.

So the kind of thing you’re talking about

is very, very, very small relative

to our experience of daily life.

Right, so I mean, you know,

we don’t know exactly the size,

but maybe 10 to the minus,

maybe around 10 to the minus 100 meters.

So, you know, the size of, to give a comparison,

the size of a proton is 10 to the minus 15 meters.

And so this is something incredibly tiny compared to that.

And the idea that from that would emerge

the experience of continuous space is mind blowing.

Well, what’s your intuition why that’s possible?

Like, first of all, I mean, we’ll get into it,

but I don’t know if we will

through the medium of conversation,

but the construct of hypergraphs is just beautiful.

Right.

Cellular automata are beautiful.

We’ll talk about it.

But this thing about, you know,

continuity arising from discrete systems

is in today’s world is actually not so surprising.

I mean, you know, your average computer screen, right?

Every computer screen is made of discrete pixels.

Yet we have the, you know,

we have the idea that we’re seeing

these continuous pictures.

I mean, it’s, you know,

the fact that on a large scale,

continuity can arise from lots of discrete elements.

This is at some level unsurprising now.

Wait, wait, wait, wait, wait, wait.

But the pixels have a very definitive structure

of neighbors on a computer screen.

Right.

There’s no concept of spatial,

of space inherent in the underlying fabric of reality.

Right, right, right.

So the point is that, but there are cases where there are.

So for example, let’s just imagine you have a square grid.

Okay, and at every point on the grid,

you have one of these atoms of space

and it’s connected to four other,

four other atoms of space on the, you know,

Northeast, Southwest corners, right?

There you have something where if you zoom out from that,

it’s like a computer screen.

Yeah, so the relationship creates the spatial,

like the relationship creates a constraint,

which then in an emergent sense creates a like,

yeah, like basically a spatial coordinate for that thing.

Yeah, right.

Even though the individual point doesn’t have a space.

Even though the individual point doesn’t know anything,

it just knows what its neighbors are.

On a large scale, it can be described by saying,

oh, it looks like it’s a, you know,

this grid is zoomed out grid.

You can say, well, you can describe these different points

by saying they have certain positions,

coordinates, et cetera.

Now, in the sort of real setup,

it’s more complicated than that.

It isn’t just a square grid or something.

It’s something much more dynamic and complicated,

which we’ll talk about.

But so, you know, the first idea,

the first key idea is, you know,

what’s the universe made of?

It’s made of atoms of space basically

with these connections between them.

What kind of connections do they have?

Well, so the simplest kind of thing you might say is,

we’ve got something like a graph

where every atom of space,

where we have these edges that go between,

these connections that go between atoms of space.

We’re not saying how long these edges are.

We’re just saying there is a connection

from this place, from this atom to this atom.

Just a quick pause,

because there’s a lot of very people that listen to this.

Just to clarify, because I did a poll actually,

what do you think a graph is a long time ago?

And it’s kind of funny how few people

know the term graph outside of computer science.

It’s good.

Let’s call it a network.

I think that’s it.

Let’s call it a network is better.

So, but every time, I like the word graph though.

So let’s define, let’s just say that a graph

will use terms nodes and edges maybe.

And it’s just the nodes represent some abstract entity

and then the edges represent relationships

between those entities.

Right, exactly.

So that’s what a graph says.

Sorry, so there you go.

So that’s the basic structure.

That is the simplest case of a basic structure.

Actually, it tends to be better to think about hypergraphs.

So a hypergraph is just, instead of saying

there are connections between pairs of things,

we say there are connections between any number of things.

So there might be ternary edges.

So instead of just having two points

are connected by an edge,

you say three points are all associated with a hyperedge,

are all connected by a hyperedge.

That’s just, at some level, that’s a detail.

It’s a detail that happens to make the, for me,

sort of in the history of this project,

the realization that you could do things that way

broke out of certain kinds of arbitrariness

that I felt that there was in the model

before I had seen how this worked.

I mean, a hypergraph can be mapped to a graph.

It’s just a convenient representation.

Mathematical speaking.

That’s correct. That’s correct.

But so then, so, okay, so the first question,

the first idea of these models of ours is

space is made of these connected sort of atoms of space.

The next idea is space is all there is.

There’s nothing except for this space.

So in traditional ideas in physics,

people have said there’s space, it’s kind of a background.

And then there’s matter, all these particles, electrons,

all these other things, which exist in space, right?

But in this model, one of the key ideas is

there’s nothing except space.

So in other words, everything that exists in the universe

is a feature of this hypergraph.

So how can that possibly be?

Well, the way that works is

that there are certain structures in this hypergraph

where you say that little twisty knotted thing,

we don’t know exactly how this works yet,

but we have sort of idea about how it works mathematically.

This sort of twisted knotted thing,

that’s the core of an electron.

This thing over there that has this different form,

that’s something else.

So the different peculiarities of the structure

of this graph are the very things

that we think of as the particles inside the space,

but in fact, it’s just a property of the space.

Mind blowing, first of all, that it’s mind blowing,

and we’ll probably talk in its simplicity and beauty.

Yes, I think it’s very beautiful.

I mean, this is, I’m…

But okay, but that’s space,

and then there’s another concept

we didn’t really kind of mention,

but you think it of computation as a transformation.

Let’s talk about time in a second.

Let’s just, I mean, on the subject of space,

there’s this question of kind of what,

there’s this idea, there is this hypergraph,

it represents space,

and it represents everything that’s in space.

The features of that hypergraph,

you can say certain features in this part we do know,

certain features of the hypergraph

represent the presence of energy, for example,

or the presence of mass or momentum,

and we know what the features of the hypergraph

that represent those things are,

but it’s all just the same hypergraph.

So one thing you might ask is,

you know, if you just look at this hypergraph and you say,

and we’re gonna talk about sort of what the hypergraph does,

but if you say, you know,

how much of what’s going on in this hypergraph

is things we know and care about,

like particles and atoms and electrons

and all this kind of thing,

and how much is just the background of space?

So it turns out, so far as in one rough estimate of this,

everything that we care about in the universe

is only one part in 10 to the 120

of what’s actually going on.

The vast majority of what’s happening

is purely things that maintain the structure of space.

That, in other words, that the things that are

the features of space that are the things

that we consider notable,

like the presence of particles and so on,

that’s a tiny little piece of froth

on the top of all this activity

that mostly is just intended to,

you know, mostly, I can’t say intended,

there’s no intention here,

that just maintains the structure of space.

Let me load that in.

It just makes me feel so good as a human being.

To be the froth on the one in a 10 to the 120

or something of, well.

And also just humbling how,

in this mathematical framework,

how much work needs to be done

on the infrastructure of our universe.

Right, to maintain the infrastructure of our universe

is a lot of work.

We are merely writing a little tiny things

on top of that infrastructure.

But you were just starting to talk a little bit about,

we talked about space,

that represents all the stuff that’s in the universe.

The question is, what does that stuff do?

And for that, we have to start talking about time

and what is time and so on.

And, you know, one of the basic idea of this model

is time is the progression of computation.

So in other words, we have a structure of space

and there is a rule that says

how that structure of space will change.

And it’s the application,

the repeated application of that rule

that defines the progress of time.

And what does the rule look like

in the space of hypergraphs?

Right, so what the rule says is something like,

if you have a little tiny piece of hypergraph

that looks like this,

then it will be transformed into a piece of hypergraph

that looks like this.

So that’s all it says.

It says you pick up these elements of space

and you can think of these edges,

these hyper edges as being relations

between elements in space.

You might pick up these two relations

between elements in space.

And we’re not saying where those elements are

or what they are,

but every time there’s a certain arrangement

of elements in space,

then arrangement in the sense of the way they’re connected,

then we transform it into some other arrangement.

So there’s a little tiny pattern

and you transform it into another little pattern.

That’s right.

And then because of this,

I mean, again, it’s kind of similar to cellular automata

in that like on paper, the rule looks like super simple.

It’s like, yeah, okay.

Yeah, right, from this, the universe can be born.

But like once you start applying it,

beautiful structure starts being,

potentially can be created.

And what you’re doing is you’re applying that rule

to different parts,

like anytime you match it within the hypergraph.

And then one of the like incredibly beautiful

and interesting things to think about

is the order in which you apply that rule,

because that pattern appears all over the place.

Right, so this is a big complicated thing,

very hard to wrap one’s brain around, okay?

So you say the rule is every time you see this little pattern

transform it in this way.

But yet, as you look around the space

that represents the universe,

there may be zillions of places

where that little pattern occurs.

So what it says is just do this,

apply this rule wherever you feel like.

And what is extremely non trivial is,

well, okay, so this is happening sort of

in computer science terms, sort of asynchronously,

you’re just doing it wherever you feel like doing it.

And the only constraint is

that if you’re going to apply the rule somewhere,

the things to which you apply the rule,

the little elements to which you apply the rule,

if they have to be,

okay, well, you can think of each application of the rule

as being kind of an event that happens in the universe.

And the input to an event has to be ready

for the event to occur.

That is, if one event occurred,

if one transformation occurred,

and it produced a particular atom of space,

then that atom of space has to already exist

before another transformation that’s going to apply

to that atom of space can occur.

So that’s like the prerequisite for the event.

That’s right, that’s right.

So that defines a kind of,

this sort of set of causal relationships between events.

It says, this event has to have happened before this event.

But that is…

But that’s not a very limiting constraint.

No, it’s not.

And what’s interesting…

You still get the zillion,

that’s a technical term, options.

That’s correct.

But, okay, so this is where things get a little bit more

elaborate, but…

But they’re mind blowing, so…

Right, but so what happens is,

so the first thing you might say is,

you know, let’s…

Well, okay, so this question about the freedom

of which event you do when.

Well, let me sort of state an answer and then explain it.

Okay, the validity of special relativity

is a consequence of the fact that in some sense,

it doesn’t matter in what order you do

these underlying things, so long as they respect

this kind of set of causal relationships.

So…

And that’s the part that’s in a certain sense

is a really important one,

but the fact that it sometimes doesn’t matter,

that’s a…

I don’t know what to…

That’s another, like, beautiful thing.

Well, okay, so there’s this idea

of what I call causal invariance.

Causal invariance, exactly.

So that’s a…

Really, really powerful idea.

Right, it’s a powerful idea,

which has actually arisen in different forms

many times in the history of mathematics,

mathematical logic, even computer science,

has many different names.

I mean, our particular version of it

is a little bit tighter than other versions,

but it’s basically the same idea.

Here’s how to think about that idea.

So imagine that…

Well, let’s talk about it in terms of math for a second.

Let’s say you’re doing algebra and you’re told,

you know, multiply out this series of polynomials

that are multiplied together, okay?

You say, well, which order should I do that in?

Say, well, do I multiply the third one by the fourth one

and then do it by the first one?

Or do I do the fifth one by the sixth one and then do that?

Well, it turns out it doesn’t matter.

You can multiply them out in any order,

you’ll always get the same answer.

That’s a property…

If you think about kind of making a kind of network

that represents in what order you do things,

you’ll get different orders

for different ways of multiplying things out,

but you’ll always get the same answer.

Same thing if you…

Let’s say you’re sorting.

You’ve got a bunch of A’s and B’s.

They’re in random, some random order,

you know, BAA, BBBAA, whatever.

And you have a little rule that says,

every time you see BA, flip it around to AB, okay?

Eventually you apply that rule enough times,

you’ll have sorted the string

so that it’s all the A’s first and then all the B’s.

Again, there are many different orders

in which you can do that to many different sort of places

where you can apply that update.

In the end, you’ll always get the string sorted the same way.

I know with sorting the string, it sounds obvious.

That’s to me surprising

that there is in complicated systems,

obviously with a string,

but in a hypergraph that the application of the rule,

asynchronous rule can lead to the same results sometimes.

Yes, yes, that is not obvious.

And it was something that, you know,

I sort of discovered that idea for these kinds of systems

and back in the 1990s.

And for various reasons, I was not satisfied

by how sort of fragile finding that particular property was.

And let me just make another point,

which is that it turns out that even if the underlying rule

does not have this property of causal invariance,

it can turn out that every observation

made by observers of the rule can,

they can impose what amounts to causal invariance

on the rule.

We can explain that.

It’s a little bit more complicated.

I mean, technically that has to do with this idea

of completions, which is something that comes up

in term rewriting systems,

automated theorem proving systems and so on.

But let’s ignore that for a second.

We can come to that later.

But is it useful to talk about observation?

Not yet.

It’s so great.

So there’s some concept of causal invariance

as you apply these rules in an asynchronous way,

you can think of those transformations as events.

So there’s this hypergraph that represents space

and all of these events happening in the space

and the graph grows in interesting complicated ways.

And eventually the froth arises of what we experience

as human existence.

So that’s it.

That’s some version of the picture,

but let’s explain a little bit more.

Exactly.

What’s a little more detail like?

Right.

Well, so one thing that is sort of surprising

in this theory is one of the sort of achievements

of 20th century physics was kind of bringing

space and time together.

That was, you know, special relativity.

People talk about space time, this sort of unified thing

where space and time kind of a mixed

and there’s a nice mathematical formalism

that in which, you know, space and time sort of appear

as part of the space time continuum,

the space time, you know, four vectors and things like this.

You know, we talk about time as the fourth dimension

and all these kinds of things.

It’s, you know, and it seems like the theory of relativity

sort of says space and time are fundamentally

the same kind of thing.

So one of the things that took a while to understand

in this approach of mine is that in my kind of approach,

space and time are really not fundamentally

the same kind of thing.

Space is the extension of this hypergraph.

Time is the kind of progress of this inexorable computation

of these rules getting applied to the hypergraph.

So it’s, they seem like very different kinds of things.

And so that at first seems like

how can that possibly be right?

How can that possibly be Lorentz invariant?

That’s the term for things being, you know,

following the rules of special relativity.

Well, it turns out that when you have causal invariants

that, and let’s see, we can, it’s worth explaining

a little bit how this works.

It’s a little bit elaborate,

but the basic point is that even though space and time

sort of come from very different places,

it turns out that the rules of sort of space time

that special relativity talks about come out of this model

when you’re looking at large enough systems.

So a way to think about this, you know,

in terms of when you’re looking at large enough systems,

the part of that story is when you look at some fluid

like water, for example, there are equations

that govern the flow of water.

Those equations are things that apply on a large scale.

If you look at the individual molecules,

they don’t know anything about those equations.

It’s just the sort of the large scale effect

of those molecules turns out to follow those equations.

And it’s the same kind of thing happening in our models.

I know this might be a small point,

but it might be a very big one.

We’ve been talking about space and time

at the lowest level of the model, which is space.

The hypergraph time is the evolution of this hypergraph.

But there’s also space time that we think about

and general relativity for your special relativity.

Like how do you go from the lowest source code

of space and time as we’re talking about

to the more traditional terminology of space and time?

So the key thing is this thing we call the causal graph.

So the causal graph is the graph

of causal relationships between events.

So every one of these little updating events,

every one of these little transformations

of the hypergraph happens somewhere in the hypergraph,

happens at some stage in the computation.

That’s an event.

That event has a causal relationship to other events

in the sense that if another event needs as its input,

the output from the first event,

there will be a causal relationship

of the future event will depend on the past event.

So you can say it has a causal connection.

And so you can make this graph

of causal relationships between events.

That graph of causal relationships,

causal invariance implies that that graph is unique.

It doesn’t matter even though you think,

oh, I’m, let’s say we were sorting a string, for example,

I did that particular transposition of characters

at this time, then I did that one, then I did this one.

Turns out if you look at the network of connections

between those updating events, that network is the same.

It’s the, if you were to, the structure.

So in other words, if you were to draw that,

if you were to put that network on a picture

of where you’re doing all the updating,

the places where you put the nodes of the network

will be different, but the way the nodes are connected

will always be the same.

So, but the causal graph is, I don’t know,

it’s kind of an observation, it’s not enforced,

it’s just emergent from a set of events.

It’s a feature of, okay, so what it is is.

The characteristic, I guess, of the way events happen.

Right, it’s an event can’t happen

until its input is ready.

And so that creates this network of causal relationships.

And that’s the causal graph.

And the thing that the next thing to realize is,

okay, we, when you’re going to observe

what happens in the universe,

you have to sort of make sense of this causal graph.

So, and you are an observer who yourself

is part of this causal graph.

And so that means, so let me give you an example

of how that works.

So imagine we have a really weird theory of physics

of the world where it says this updating process,

there’s only gonna be one update at every moment in time.

And there’s just gonna be like a Turing machine.

It has a little head that runs around

and just is always just updating one thing at a time.

So you say, I have a theory of physics

and the theory of physics says,

there’s just this one little place where things get updated.

You say, that’s completely crazy because,

it’s plainly obvious that things are being updated

sort of at the same time.

Async obviously, yeah, at the same time, yeah.

But the fact is that the thing is that if I’m talking to you

and you seem to be being updated as I’m being updated,

but if there’s just this one little head

that’s running around updating things,

I will not know whether you’ve been updated or not

until I’m updated.

So in other words, draw this causal graph

of the causal relationship between the updatings in you

and the updatings in me,

it’ll still be the same causal graph,

whether even though the underlying sort of story

of what happens is, oh, there’s just this one little thing

and it goes and updates in different places in the universe.

So is that clear or is that a hypothesis?

Is that clear that there’s a unique causal graph?

If there’s causal invariance, there’s unique causal graph.

So it’s okay to think of what we’re talking about

as a hypergraph and the operations on it

as a kind of touring machine with a single head,

like a single guy running around updating stuff.

Is that safe to intuitively think of it this way?

Let me think about that for a second.

Yes, I think so.

I think there’s nothing, it doesn’t matter.

I mean, you can say, okay, there is one,

the reason I’m pausing for a second is that I’m wondering,

well, when you say running around,

depends how far it jumps every time it runs.

Yeah, yeah, that’s right.

But I mean like one operation at a time.

Yeah, you can think of it as one operation at a time.

It’s easier for the human brain to think of it that way

as opposed to simultaneous.

Well, maybe it’s not, okay, but the thing is

that’s not how we experience the world.

What we experience is we look around,

everything seems to be happening

at successive moments in time everywhere in space.

Yes.

That is the, and that’s partly a feature

of our particular construction.

I mean, that is the speed of light is really fast

compared to, you know, we look around, you know,

I can see maybe a hundred feet away right now.

You know, it’s the, my brain does not process very much

in the time it takes light to go a hundred feet.

The brain operates at a scale of hundreds of milliseconds

or something like that, I don’t know.

Right.

And speed of light is much faster.

Right, you know, light goes,

in a billionth of a second light has gone afoot.

So it goes a billion feet every second.

There’s certain moments through this conversation

where I imagine the absurdity of the fact

that there’s two descendants of apes modeled by a hypergraph

that are communicating with each other

and experiencing this whole thing

as a real time simultaneous update with,

I’m taking in photons from you right now,

but there’s something much, much deeper going on here.

Right, it does have a.

It’s paralyzing sometimes to just.

Yes.

To remember that.

Right, no, I mean, you know, it’s a, you know.

Sorry.

Yes, yes, no.

As a small little tangent, I just remembered

that we’re talking about,

I mean, about the fabric of reality.

Right, so we’ve got this causal graph

that represents the sort of causal relationships

between all these events in the universe.

That causal graph kind of is a representation of space time,

but our experience of it requires

that we pick reference frames.

This is kind of a key idea.

Einstein had this idea that what that means is

we have to say, what are we going to pick

as being the sort of what we define

as simultaneous moments in time?

So for example, we can say, you know,

how do we set our clocks?

You know, if we’ve got a spacecraft landing on Mars,

you know, do we say that, you know,

what time is it landing at?

Was it, you know, even though there’s a 20 minute

speed of light delay or something, you know,

what time do we say it landed at?

How do we set up sort of time coordinates for the world?

And that turns out to be that there’s kind of

this arbitrariness to how we set these reference frames

that defines sort of what counts as simultaneous.

And what is the essence of special relativity

is to think about reference frames going at different speeds

and to think about sort of how they assign,

what counts as space, what counts as time and so on.

That’s all a bit technical, but the basic bottom line is

that this causal invariance property,

that means that it’s always the same causal graph,

independent of how you slice it with these reference frames,

you’ll always sort of see the same physical processes go on.

And that’s basically why special relativity works.

So there’s something like special relativity,

like everything around space and time

that fits this idea of the causal graph.

Right, well, you know, one way to think about it is

given that you have a basic structure

that just involves updating things in these,

you know, connected updates and looking at

the causal relationships between connected updates,

that’s enough when you unravel the consequences of that,

that together with the fact that there are lots

of these things and that you can take a continuum limit

and so on implies special relativity.

And so that, it’s kind of not a big deal

because it’s kind of a, you know,

it was completely unobvious when you started off

with saying, we’ve got this graph,

it’s being updated in time, et cetera, et cetera, et cetera,

that just looks like nothing to do with special relativity.

And yet you get that.

And what, I mean, then the thing,

I mean, this was stuff that I figured out back in the 1990s.

The next big thing you get is general relativity.

And so in this hypergraph,

the sort of limiting structure,

when you have a very big hypergraph,

you can think of as being just like, you know,

water seems continuous on a large scale.

So this hypergraph seems continuous on a large scale.

One question is, you know,

how many dimensions of space does it correspond to?

So one question you can ask is,

if you’ve just got a bunch of points

and they’re connected together,

how do you deduce what effective dimension of space

that bundle of points corresponds to?

And that’s pretty easy to explain.

So basically if you say you’ve got a point

and you look at how many neighbors does that point have?

Okay, imagine it’s on a square grid.

Then it’ll have four neighbors.

Go another level out.

How many neighbors do you get then?

What you realize is as you go more and more levels out,

as you go more and more distance on the graph out,

you’re capturing something which is essentially a circle

in two dimensions so that, you know,

the number of the area of a circle is pi R squared.

So it’s the number of points that you get to

goes up like the distance you’ve gone squared.

And in general, in D dimensional space,

it’s R to the power D.

It’s the number of points you get to

if you go R steps on the graph grows like

the number of steps you go to the power of the dimension.

And that’s a way that you can estimate

the effective dimension of one of these graphs.

So what does that grow to?

So how does the dimension grow?

There’s a, I mean, obviously the visual aspect

of these hypergraphs,

they’re often visualized in three dimensions.

Right.

So there’s a certain kind of structure,

like you said, there’s, I mean, a circle, a sphere,

there’s a planar aspect to it,

to this graph to where it kind of,

it almost starts creating a surface,

like a complicated surface, but a surface.

So how does that connect to effective dimension?

Okay, so if you can lay out the graph

in such a way that the points in the graph that,

you know, the points that are neighbors on the graph

are neighbors as you lay them out,

and you can do that in two dimensions,

then it’s gonna approximate a two dimensional thing.

If you can’t do that in two dimensions,

if everything would have to fold over a lot

in two dimensions,

then it’s not approximating a two dimensional thing.

Maybe you can lay it out in three dimensions.

Maybe you have to lay it out in five dimensions

to have it be the case

that it sort of smoothly lays out like that.

Well, but okay, so I apologize

for the different tangent questions,

but you know, there’s an infinity number of possible rules.

So we have to look for rules

that create the kind of structures

that are reminiscent for,

that have echoes of the different physics theories in them.

So what kind of rules,

is there something simple to be said

about the kind of rules that you have found beautiful,

that you have found powerful?

Right, so I mean, what, you know,

one of the features of computational irreducibility is,

it’s very, you can’t say in advance,

what’s gonna happen with any particular,

you can’t say, I’m gonna pick these rules

from this part of rule space, so to speak,

because they’re gonna be the ones that are gonna work.

That’s, you can make some statements along those lines,

but you can’t generally say that.

Now, you know, the state of what we’ve been able to do

is, you know, different properties of the universe,

like dimensionality, you know, integer dimensionality,

features of other features of quantum mechanics,

things like that.

At this point, what we’ve got is,

we’ve got rules that any one of those features,

we can get a rule that has that feature.

Yeah, so the.

We don’t have the sort of, the final,

here’s a rule which has all of these features,

we do not have that yet.

So if I were to try to summarize

the Wolfram physics project, which is, you know,

something that’s been in your brain for a long time,

but really has just exploded in activity,

you know, only just months ago.

Yes.

So it’s an evolving thing, and next week,

I’ll try to publish this conversation

as quickly as possible, because by the time it’s published,

already new things will probably have come out.

So if I were to summarize it,

we’ve talked about the basics of,

there’s a hypergraph that represents space,

there is transformations in that hypergraph

that represents time.

The progress of time.

The progress of time, there’s a causal graph

that’s a characteristic of this,

and the basic process of science,

of, yeah, of science within the Wolfram physics model

is to try different rules and see which properties

of physics that we know of, known physical theories,

are, appear within the graphs that emerge from that rule.

That’s what I thought it was going to be.

Uh oh, okay.

So what is it?

It turns out we can do a lot better than that.

It turns out that using kind of mathematical ideas,

we can say, and computational ideas,

we can make general statements,

and those general statements turn out to correspond

to things that we know from 20th century physics.

In other words, the idea of you just try a bunch of rules

and see what they do,

that’s what I thought we were gonna have to do.

But in fact, we can say, given causal invariance

and computational irreducibility, we can derive,

and this is where it gets really pretty interesting,

we can derive special relativity,

we can derive general relativity,

we can derive quantum mechanics.

And that’s where things really start to get exciting,

is, you know, it wasn’t at all obvious to me

that even if we were completely correct,

and even if we had, you know, this is the rule,

you know, even if we found the rule,

to be able to say, yes, it corresponds

to things we already know,

I did not expect that to be the case.

And…

So for somebody who is a simple mind

and definitely not a physicist, not even close,

what does derivation mean in this case?

Okay, so let me, this is an interesting question.

Okay, so there’s, so one thing…

In the context of computational irreducibility.

Yeah, yeah, right, right.

So what you have to do, let me go back to, again,

the mundane example of fluids and water

and things like that, right?

So you have a bunch of molecules bouncing around.

You can say, just as a piece of mathematics,

I happen to do this from cellular automata

back in the mid 1980s, you can say,

just as a matter of mathematics,

you can say the continuum limit

of these little molecules bouncing around

is the Navier Stokes equations.

That’s just a piece of mathematics.

It’s not, it doesn’t rely on…

You have to make certain assumptions

that you have to say there’s enough randomness

in the way the molecules bounce around

that certain statistical averages work,

et cetera, et cetera, et cetera.

Okay, it is a very similar derivation

to derive, for example, the Einstein equations.

Okay, so the way that works, roughly,

the Einstein equations are about curvature of space.

Curvature of space, I talked about sort of

how you can figure out dimension of space.

There’s a similar kind of way of figuring out

if you just sort of say, you know,

you’re making a larger and larger ball

or larger and larger, if you draw a circle

on the surface of the earth, for example,

you might think the area of a circle is pi r squared,

but on the surface of the earth,

because it’s a sphere, it’s not flat,

the area of a circle isn’t precisely pi r squared.

As the circle gets bigger, the area is slightly smaller

than you would expect from the formula pi r squared

as a little correction term that depends on the ratio

of the size of the circle to the radius of the earth.

Okay, so it’s the same basic thing,

allows you to measure from one of these hypergraphs

what is its effective curvature.

And that’s…

So the little piece of mathematics

that explains special general relativity

can map nicely to describe fundamental property

of the hypergraphs, the curvature of the hypergraphs.

So special relativity is about the relationship

of time to space.

General relativity is about curvature

and this space represented by this hypergraph.

So what is the curvature of a hypergraph?

Okay, so first I have to explain,

what we’re explaining is,

first thing you have to have is a notion of dimension.

You don’t get to talk about curvature of things.

If you say, oh, it’s a curved line,

but I don’t know what a line is yet.

So…

Yeah, what is the dimension of a hypergraph then?

From where, we’ve talked about effective dimension, but…

Right, that’s what this is about.

What this is about is, you have your hypergraph,

it’s got a trillion nodes in it.

What is it roughly like?

Is it roughly like a grid, a two dimensional grid?

Is it roughly like all those nodes are arranged online?

What’s it roughly like?

And there’s a pretty simple mathematical way

to estimate that by just looking at this thing

I was describing, this sort of the size of a ball

that you construct in the hypergraph.

That’s a, you just measure that,

you can just compute it on a computer for a given hypergraph

and you can say, oh, this thing is wiggling around,

but it’s roughly corresponds to two or something like that,

or roughly corresponds to 2.6 or whatever.

So that’s how you have a notion of dimension

in these hypergraphs.

Curvature is something a little bit beyond that.

If you look at how the size of this ball increases

as you increase its radius,

curvature is a correction

to the size increase associated with dimension.

It’s a sort of a second order term

in determining the size.

Just like the area of a circle is roughly pi R squared.

So it goes up like R squared.

The two is because it’s in two dimensions,

but when that circle is drawn on a big sphere,

the actual formula is pi R squared times one minus

R squared over A squared and some coefficient.

So in other words, there’s a correction to,

and that correction term, that gives you curvature.

And that correction term

is what makes this hypergraph correspond,

have the potential to correspond to curved space.

Now, the next question is, is that curvature,

is the way that curvature works

the way that Einstein’s equations for general relativity,

is it the way they say it should work?

And the answer is yes.

And so how does that work?

The calculation of the curvature of this hypergraph

for some set of rules?

No, it doesn’t matter what the rules are.

So long as they have causal invariance

and computational irreducibility,

and they lead to finite dimensional space,

noninfinite dimensional space.

Noninfinite dimensional.

It can grow infinitely,

but it can’t be infinite dimensional.

So what is a infinitely dimensional hypergraph look like?

So that means, for example, so in a tree,

you start from one root of the tree,

it doubles, doubles again, doubles again, doubles again.

And that means if you ask the question,

starting from a given point,

how many points do you get to?

Remember, in like a circle,

you get to R squared, the two there.

On a tree, you get to, for example, two to the R.

It’s exponential dimensional, so to speak,

or infinite dimensional.

Do you have a sense of, in the space of all possible rules,

how many lead to infinitely dimensional hypergraphs?

Is that? No.

Okay.

Is that an important thing to know?

Yes, it’s an important thing to know.

I would love to know the answer to that.

But it gets a little bit more complicated

because, for example, it’s very possibly the case

that in our physical universe,

that the universe started infinite dimensional.

And it only, as the Big Bang,

it was very likely infinite dimensional.

And as the universe sort of expanded and cooled,

its dimension gradually went down.

And so one of the bizarre possibilities,

which actually there are experiments you can do

to try and look at this,

the universe can have dimension fluctuations.

So in other words,

we think we live in a three dimensional universe,

but actually there may be places

where it’s actually 3.01 dimensional,

or where it’s 2.99 dimensional.

And it may be that in the very early universe,

it was actually infinite dimensional,

and it’s only a late stage phenomenon

that we end up getting three dimensional space.

But from your perspective of the hypergraph,

one of the underlying assumptions you kind of implied,

but you have a sense, a hope set of assumptions

that the rules that underlie our universe,

or the rule that underlies our universe is static.

Is that one of the assumptions

you’re currently operating under?

Yes, but there’s a footnote to that,

which we should get to,

because it requires a few more steps.

Well, actually then, let’s backtrack to the curvature,

because we’re talking about as long as it’s finite dimensional.

Finite dimensional computational irreducibility

and causal invariance,

then it follows that the large scale structure

will follow Einstein’s equations.

And now let me again, qualify that a little bit more,

there’s a little bit more complexity to it.

The, okay, so Einstein’s equations in their simplest form

apply to the vacuum, no matter, just the vacuum.

And they say, in particular, what they say is,

if you have, so there’s this term GD6,

that’s a term that means shortest path,

comes from measuring the shortest paths on the Earth.

So you look at a bunch of, a bundle of GD6,

a bunch of shortest paths,

it’s like the paths that photons

would take between two points.

Then the statement of Einstein’s equations,

it’s basically a statement about a certain the,

that as you look at a bundle of GD6,

the structure of space has to be such that,

although the cross sectional area of this bundle may,

although the actual shape of the cross section may change,

the cross sectional area does not.

That’s a version, that’s the most simple minded version

of R mu nu minus a half R G mu nu equals zero,

which is the more mathematical version

of Einstein’s equations.

It’s a statement of the thing called the Ritchie tensor

is equal to zero.

That’s Einstein’s equations for the vacuum.

Okay, so we get that as a result of this model,

but footnote, big footnote,

because all the matter in the universe

is the stuff we actually care about.

The vacuum is not stuff we care about.

So the question is, how does matter come into this?

And for that, you have to understand what energy is

in these models.

And one of the things that we realized, you know,

late last year was that there’s a very simple interpretation

of energy in these models, okay?

And energy is basically, well, intuitively,

it’s the amount of activity in these hypergraphs

and the way that that remains over time.

So a little bit more formally,

you can think about this causal graph

as having these edges that represent causal relationships.

You can think about, oh boy,

there’s one more concept that we didn’t get to.

It’s the notion of space like hypersurfaces.

So this is not as scary as it sounds.

It’s a common notion in general activity.

The notion is you are defining what is a possibly,

where in space time might be a particular moment in time.

So in other words, what is a consistent set of places

where you can say, this is happening now, so to speak.

And you make the series of sort of slices

through the space time, through this causal graph

to represent sort of what we consider

to be successive moments in time.

It’s somewhat arbitrary because you can deform that

if you’re going at a different speed in a special activity,

you tip those things, there are different kinds

of deformations, but only certain deformations

are allowed by the structure of the causal graph.

Anyway, be that as it may, the basic point is

there is a way of figuring out,

you say, what is the energy associated

with what’s going on in this hypergraph?

And the answer is there is a precise definition of that.

And it is the formal way to say it is,

it’s the flux of causal edges

through space like hypersurfaces.

The slightly less formal way to say it,

it’s basically the amount of activity.

See, the reason it gets tricky is you might say

it’s the amount of activity per unit volume

in this hypergraph, but you haven’t defined what volume is.

So it’s a little bit, you have to be a little more careful.

But this hypersurface gives some more formalism to that.

Yeah, yeah, it gives a way to connect that.

But intuitive, we should think about as the just activity.

Right, so the amount of activity that kind of remains

in one place in the hypergraph corresponds to energy.

The amount of activity that is kind of where an activity here

affects an activity somewhere else,

corresponds to momentum.

And so one of the things that’s kind of cool

is that I’m trying to think about

how to say this intuitively.

The mathematics is easy,

but the intuitive version, I’m not sure.

But basically the way that things sort of stay

in the same place and have activity

is associated with rest mass.

And so one of the things that you get to derive

is E equals MC squared.

That is a consequence of this interpretation of energy

in terms of the way the causal graph works,

which is the whole thing is sort of a consequence

of this whole story about updates and hypergraphs and so on.

So can you linger on that a little bit?

How do we get E equals MC squared?

So where does the mass come from?

Okay, okay.

I mean, is there an intuitive, it’s okay.

First of all, you’re pretty deep

in the mathematical explorations of this thing right now.

We’re in a very, we’re in a flux currently.

So maybe you haven’t even had time

to think about intuitive explanations, but.

Yeah, I mean, this one is, look, roughly what’s happening,

that derivation is actually rather easy.

And everybody, and I’ve been saying

we should pay more attention to this derivation

because it’s such, you know,

cause people care about this one.

But everybody says, it’s just easy.

It’s easy.

So there’s some concept of energy

that can be intuitively thought of as the activity,

the flux, the level of changes that are occurring

based on the transformations within a certain volume,

however the heck do you find the volume.

Okay, so, and then mass.

Well, mass is associated with kind of the energy

that does not cause you to,

that does not somehow propagate through time.

Yeah, I mean, one of the things that was not obvious

in the usual formulation of special relativity

is that space and time are connected in a certain way.

Energy and momentum are also connected in a certain way.

The fact that the connection of energy to momentum

is analogous to the connection to space

between space and time

is not self evident in ordinary relativity.

It is a consequence of this, of the way this model works.

It’s an intrinsic consequence of the way this model works.

And it’s all to do with that,

with unraveling that connection

that ends up giving you this relationship

between energy and, well, it’s energy, momentum, mass,

they’re all connected.

And so like, that’s hence the general relativity.

You have a sense that it appears to be baked in

to the fundamental properties

of the way these hypergraphs are evolved.

Well, I didn’t yet get to,

so I got as far as special relativity and equals MC squared.

The one last step is, in general relativity,

the final connection is energy and mass

cause curvature in space.

And that’s something that when you understand

this interpretation of energy,

and you kind of understand the correspondence

to curvature and hypergraphs,

then you can finally sort of, the big final answer is,

you derive the full version of Einstein’s equations

for space, time and matter.

And that’s some.

Is that, have you, that last piece with curvature,

have, is that, have you arrived there yet?

Oh yeah, we’re there, yes.

And here’s the way that we,

here’s how we’re really, really going to know

we’ve arrived, okay?

So, you know, we have the mathematical derivation,

it’s all fine, but, you know,

mathematical derivations, okay.

So one thing that’s sort of a,

you know, we’re taking this limit

of what happens when you, the limit,

you have to look at things which are large

compared to the size of an elementary length,

small compared to the whole size of the universe,

large compared to certain kinds of fluctuations,

blah, blah, blah.

There’s a, there’s a, there’s a tower

of many, many of these mathematical limits

that have to be taken.

So if you’re a pure mathematician saying,

where’s the precise proof?

It’s like, well, there are all these limits,

we can, you know, we can try each one of them

computationally and we could say, yeah, it really works,

but the formal mathematics is really hard to do.

I mean, for example, in the case of deriving

the equations of fluid dynamics from molecular dynamics,

that derivation has never been done.

There is no rigorous version of that derivation.

So, so that could be.

Because you can’t do the limits?

Yeah, because you can’t do the limits.

But so the limits allow you to try to describe

something general about the system

and very, very particular kinds of limits that you need

to take with these very.

Right, and the limits will definitely work

the way we think they work.

And we can do all kinds of computer experiments.

It’s just a hard derivation.

Yeah, it’s just, it’s just the mathematical structure

kind of, you know, ends up running right into

computational irreducibility.

And you end up with a bunch of, a bunch of difficulty there.

But here’s the way that we’re getting really confident

that we know completely what we’re talking about,

which is when people study things like black hole mergers,

using Einstein’s equations, what do they actually do?

Well, they actually use Mathematica or a whole bunch

to analyze the equations and so on.

But in the end, they do numerical relativity,

which means they take these nice mathematical equations

and they break them down so that they can run them

on a computer.

And they break them down into something

which is actually a discrete approximation

to these equations.

Then they run them on a computer, they get results.

Then you look at the gravitational waves

and you see if they match, okay?

It turns out that our model gives you a direct way

to do numerical relativity.

So in other words, instead of saying,

you start from these continuum equations from Einstein,

you break them down into these discrete things,

you run them on a computer,

you say, we’re doing it the other way around.

We’re starting from these discrete things

that come from our model.

And we’re just running big versions on the computer.

And, you know, what we’re saying is,

and this is how things will work.

So the way I’m calling this is proof by compilation,

so to speak, that is, in other words,

you’re taking something where, you know,

we’ve got this description of a black hole system.

And what we’re doing is we’re showing that the, you know,

what we get by just running our model agrees

with what you would get by doing the computation

from the Einstein equations.

As a small tangent or actually a very big tangent,

but proof by compilation is a beautiful concept.

In a sense, the way of doing physics with this model

is by running it or compiling it.

And have you thought about,

and these things can be very large,

is there a totally new possibilities of computing hardware

and computing software,

which allows you to perform this kind of compilation?

Well, algorithms, software, hardware.

So first comment is these models seem to give one

a lot of intuition about distributed computing,

a lot of different intuition about how to think

about parallel computation.

And that particularly comes from the quantum mechanics

side of things, which we didn’t talk about much yet.

But the question of what, you know,

given our current computer hardware,

how can we most efficiently simulate things?

That’s actually partly a story of the model itself,

because the model itself has deep parallelism in it.

The ways that we are simulating it,

we’re just starting to be able to use that deep parallelism

to be able to be more efficient

in the way that we simulate things.

But in fact, the structure of the model itself

allows us to think about parallel computation

in different ways.

And one of my realizations is that, you know,

so it’s very hard to get in your brain

how you deal with parallel computation.

And you’re always worrying about, you know,

if multiple things can happen on different computers

at different times, oh, what happens

if this thing happens before that thing?

And we’ve really got, you know,

we have these race conditions where something can race

to get to the answer before another thing.

And you get all tangled up because you don’t know

which thing is gonna come in first.

And usually when you do parallel computing,

there’s a big obsession to lock things down

to the point where you’ve had locks and mutexes

and God knows what else,

where you’ve arranged it so that there can only be

one sequence of things that can happen.

So you don’t have to think about

all the different kinds of things that can happen.

Well, in these models, physics is throwing us into,

forcing us to think about all these possible things

that can happen.

But these models together with what we know from physics

is giving us new ways to think about

all possible things happening,

about all these different things happening in parallel.

And so I’m guessing…

They have built in protection for some of the parallelism.

Well, causal invariance is the built in protection.

Causal invariance is what means that

even though things happen in different orders,

it doesn’t matter in the end.

As a person who struggled with concurrent programming

in like Java,

with all the basic concepts of concurrent programming,

that if there could be built up

a strong mathematical framework for causal invariance,

that’s so liberating.

And that could be not just liberating,

but really powerful for massively distributed computation.

Absolutely.

No, I mean, what’s eventual consistency

in distributed databases

is essentially the causal invariance idea.

Yeah. Okay.

So that’s…

But have you thought about,

like really large simulations?

Yeah. I mean, I’m also thinking about,

look, the fact is I’ve spent much of my life

as a language designer, right?

So I can’t possibly not think about,

what does this mean for designing languages

for parallel computation?

In fact, another thing that’s one of these…

I’m always embarrassed at how long it’s taken me

to figure stuff out.

But back in the 1980s,

I worked on trying to make up languages

for parallel computation.

I thought about doing graph rewriting.

I thought about doing these kinds of things,

but I couldn’t see how to actually make the connections

to actually do something useful.

I think now physics is kind of showing us

how to make those things useful.

And so my guess is that in time,

we’ll be talking about, we do parallel programming.

We’ll be talking about programming

in a certain reference frame,

just as we think about thinking about physics

in a certain reference frame.

It’s a certain coordination of what’s going on.

We say, we’re gonna program in this reference frame.

Oh, let’s change the reference frame

to this reference frame.

And then our program will seem different

and we’ll have a different way to think about it.

But it’s still the same program underneath.

So let me ask on this topic,

cause I put out that I’m talking to you.

I got way more questions than I can deal with,

but what pops to mind is a question somebody asked

on Reddit I think is, please ask Dr. Wolfram,

what are the specs of the computer running the universe?

So we’re talking about specs of hardware and software

for simulations of a large scale thing.

What about a scale that is comparative

to something that eventually leads

to the two of us talking and about?

Right, right, right.

So actually I did try to estimate that.

And we actually have to go a couple more stages

before we can really get to that answer

because we’re talking about this thing.

This is what happens when you build these abstract systems

and you’re trying to explain the universe,

they’re quite a number of levels deep, so to speak.

But the…

You mean conceptually or like literally?

Cause you’re talking about small objects

and there’s 10 to the 120 something.

Yeah, right.

It is conceptually deep.

And one of the things that’s happening sort of structurally

in this project is, you know, there were ideas,

there’s another layer of ideas,

there’s another layer of ideas

to get to the different things that correspond to physics.

They’re just different layers of ideas.

And they are, you know, it’s actually probably,

if anything, getting harder to explain this project

cause I’m realizing that the fraction of way through

that I am so far and explaining this to you is less than,

than, you know, it might be because we know more now,

you know, every week basically we know a little bit more.

And like…

Those are just layers on the initial fundamental structure.

Yes, but the layers are, you know,

you might be asking me, you know,

how do we get the difference between fermions and bosons,

the difference between particles

that can be all in the same state

and particles that exclude each other, okay.

Last three days, we’ve kind of figured that out.

Okay.

But, and it’s very interesting.

It’s very cool.

And it’s very…

And those are some kind of properties at a certain level,

layer of abstraction on the graph.

Yes, yes.

And there’s, but the layers of abstraction are kind of,

they’re compounding.

Stacking up.

So it’s difficult, but…

But okay.

But the specs nevertheless remain the same.

Okay, the specs underneath.

So I have an estimate.

So the question is, what are the units?

So we’ve got these different fundamental constants

about the world.

So one of them is the speed of light, which is the…

So the thing that’s always the same

in all these different ways of thinking about the universe

is the notion of time, because time is computation.

And so there’s an elementary time,

which is sort of the amount of time that we ascribe

to elapsing in a single computational step.

Yeah.

Okay.

So that’s the elementary time.

So then there’s an elementary…

That’s a parameter or whatever.

That’s a constant.

It’s whatever we define it to be,

because I mean, we don’t, you know…

I mean, it’s all relative, right?

It doesn’t matter.

Yes, it doesn’t matter what it is,

because we could be, it could be slower.

It’s just a number which we use to convert that

to seconds, so to speak,

because we are experiencing things

and we say this amount of time has elapsed, so to speak.

But we’re within this thing.

Absolutely.

So it doesn’t matter, right?

But what does matter is the ratio,

what we can, the ratio of the spatial distance

and this hypergraph to this moment of time.

Again, that’s an arbitrary thing,

but we measure that in meters per second, for example,

and that ratio is the speed of light.

So the ratio of the elementary distance

to the elementary time is the speed of light, okay?

Perfect.

And so there’s another,

there are two other levels of this, okay?

So there is a thing which we can talk about,

which is the maximum entanglement speed,

which is a thing that happens at another level

in this whole sort of story

of how these things get constructed.

That’s a sort of maximum speed in quantum,

in the space of quantum states.

Just as the speed of light

is a maximum speed in physical space,

this is a maximum speed in the space of quantum states.

There’s another level which is associated

with what we call ruleal space,

which is another one of these maximum speeds.

We’ll get to this.

So these are limitations on the system

that are able to capture the kind of physical universe

which we live in.

The quantum mechanical.

There are inevitable features of having a rule

that has only a finite amount of information in the rule.

So long as you have a rule that only involves

a bounded amount, a limited amount of,

only involving a limited number of elements,

limited number of relations,

it is inevitable that there are these speed constraints.

We knew about the one for speed of light.

We didn’t know about the one for maximum entanglement speed,

which is actually something that is possibly measurable,

particularly in black hole systems and things like this.

Anyway, this is long, long story short.

You’re asking what the processing specs of the universe,

of the sort of computation of the universe.

There’s a question of even what are the units

of some of these measurements, okay?

So the units I’m using are Wolfram language instructions

per second, okay?

Because you gotta have some,

what computation are you doing?

There gotta be some kind of frame of reference.

Right, right.

So, because it turns out in the end,

there will be, there’s sort of an arbitrariness

in the language that you use to describe the universe.

So in those terms, I think it’s like 10 to the 500,

Wolfram language operations per second, I think,

is the, I think it’s of that order.

You know, basically.

So that’s the scale of the computation.

What about memory?

If there’s an interesting thing to say

about storage and memory.

Well, there’s a question of how many sort of atoms

of space might there be?

You know, maybe 10 to the 400.

We don’t know exactly how to estimate these numbers.

I mean, this is based on some, I would say,

somewhat rickety way of estimating things.

You know, when there start to be able to be experiments done,

if we’re lucky, there will be experiments

that can actually nail down some of these numbers.

And because of computation reducibility,

there’s not much hope for very efficient compression,

like very efficient representation

of this atom space? Good question.

I mean, there’s probably certain things, you know,

the fact that we can deduce anything,

okay, the question is how deep does the reducibility go?

Right. Okay.

And I keep on being surprised

that it’s a lot deeper than I thought.

Okay, and so one of the things is that,

that there’s a question of sort of how much

of the whole of physics do we have to be able to get

in order to explain certain kinds of phenomena?

Like for example, if we want to study quantum interference,

do we have to know what an electron is?

Turns out I thought we did, turns out we don’t.

I thought to know what energy is,

we would have to know what electrons were.

We don’t.

So you get a lot of really powerful shortcuts.

Right.

There’s a bunch of sort of bulk information about the world.

The thing that I’m excited about last few days, okay,

is the idea of fermions versus bosons, fundamental idea

that I mean, it’s the reason we have matter

that doesn’t just self destruct,

is because of the exclusion principle

that means that two electrons can never be

in the same quantum state.

Is it useful for us to maybe first talk

about how quantum mechanics fits

into the Wolfram physics model?

Yes.

Let’s go there.

So we talked about general relativity.

Now, what have you found from quantum mechanics

within and outside of the Wolfram physics?

Right, so I mean, the key idea of quantum mechanics

that sort of the typical interpretation

is classical physics says a definite thing happens.

Quantum physics says there’s this whole set of paths

of things that might happen.

And we are just observing some overall probability

of how those paths work.

Okay, so when you think about our hypergraphs

and all these little updates that are going on,

there’s a very remarkable thing to realize,

which is if you say, well,

which particular sequence of updates should you do?

Say, well, it’s not really defined.

You can do any of a whole collection

of possible sequences of updates.

Okay, that set of possible sequences of updates

defines yet another kind of graph

that we call a multiway graph.

And a multiway graph just is a graph

where at every node, there is a choice

of several different possible things that could happen.

So for example, you go this way, you go that way.

Those are two different edges in the multiway graph.

And you’re building up the set of possibilities.

So actually, like, for example, I just made the one,

the multiway graph for tic tac toe, okay?

So tic tac toe, you start off with some board

that, you know, is everything is blank,

and then somebody can put down an X somewhere,

an O somewhere, and then there are different possibilities.

At each stage, there are different possibilities.

And so you build up this multiway graph

of all those possibilities.

Now notice that even in tic tac toe,

you have the feature that there can be something

where you have two different things that happen

and then those branches merge

because you end up with the same shape,

you know, the same configuration of the board,

even though you got there in two different ways.

So the thing that’s sort of an inevitable feature

of our models is that just like quantum mechanics suggests,

definite things don’t happen.

Instead, you get this whole multiway graph

of all these possibilities.

Okay, so then the question is, so, okay,

so that’s sort of a picture of what’s going on.

Now you say, okay, well, quantum mechanics

has all these features of, you know,

all this mathematical structure and so on.

How do you get that mathematical structure?

Okay, a couple of things to say.

So quantum mechanics is actually, in a sense,

two different theories glued together.

Quantum mechanics is the theory

of how quantum amplitudes work

that more or less give you the probabilities

of things happening.

And it’s the theory of quantum measurement,

which is the theory of how we actually

conclude definite things.

Because the mathematics just gives you

these quantum amplitudes, which are more or less

probabilities of things happening,

but yet we actually observe definite things in the world.

Quantum measurement has always been a bit mysterious.

It’s always been something where people just say,

well, the mathematics says this,

but then you do a measurement,

and there are philosophical arguments

about what the measurement is.

But it’s not something where there’s a theory

of the measurement.

Somebody on Reddit also asked,

please ask Stephen to tell his story

of the double slit experiment.

Okay, yeah, I can.

Is that, does that make sense?

Oh yeah, it makes sense.

Absolutely makes sense.

Why, is this like a good way to discuss?

A little bit.

Let me go, let me explain a couple of things first.

So the structure of quantum mechanics

is mathematically quite complicated.

One of the features, let’s see,

well, how to describe this.

Okay, so first point is there’s this multiway graph

of all these different paths of things

that can happen in the world.

And the important point is that these,

you can have branchings and you can have mergings.

Okay, so this property turns out causal invariance

is the statement that the number of mergings

is equal to the number of branchings.

Yeah.

So in other words, every time there’s a branch,

eventually there will also be a merge.

In other words, every time there were two possibilities

for what might’ve happened, eventually those will merge.

Beautiful concept by the way, but yeah, yeah, yeah.

So that idea, okay, so then, so that’s one thing

and that’s closely related to the sort of objectivity

in quantum mechanics.

The fact that we believe definite things happen,

it’s because although there are all these different paths,

in some sense, because of causal invariance,

they all imply the same thing.

I’m cheating a little bit in saying that,

but that’s roughly the essence of what’s going on.

Okay, next thing to think about

is you have this multiway graph,

it has all these different possible things

that are happening.

Now we ask, this multiway graph

is sort of evolving with time.

Over time, it’s branching, it’s merging,

it’s doing all these things, okay?

Question we can ask is if we slice it at a particular time,

what do we see?

And that slice represents in a sense,

something to do with the state of the universe

at a particular time.

So in other words, we’ve got this multiway graph

of all these possibilities,

and then we’re asking, okay, we take the slice,

this slice represents, okay,

each of these different paths

corresponds to a different quantum possibility

for what’s happening.

When we take the slice, we’re saying,

what are the set of quantum possibilities

that exist at a particular time?

And when you say slice, you slice the graph

and then there’s a bunch of leaves.

A bunch of leaves.

Those represent the state of things.

Right, but then, okay, so the important thing

that you are quickly picking up on

is that what matters is kind of

how these leaves are related to each other.

So a good way to tell how leaves are related

is just to say on the step before

do they have a common ancestor?

So two leaves might be,

they might have just branched from one thing

or they might be far away,

way far apart in this graph

where to get to a common ancestor,

maybe you have to go all the way back

to the beginning of the graph,

all the way back to the beginning.

So there’s some kind of measure of distance.

Right, but what you get is by making the slice,

we call it branchial space, the space of branches.

And in this branchial space,

you have a graph that represents the relationships

between these quantum states in branchial space.

You have this notion of distance in branchial space.

Okay, so.

It’s connected to quantum entanglement.

Yes, yes, it’s basically,

the distance in branchial space

is kind of an entanglement distance.

So this.

That’s a very nice model.

Right, it is very nice, it’s very beautiful.

I mean, it’s so clean.

I mean, it’s really, and it tells one,

okay, so anyway, so then this branchial space

has this sort of map of the entanglements

between quantum states.

So in physical space, we have,

so you can say, take, let’s say the causal graph,

and we can slice that at a particular time,

and then we get this map

of how things are laid out in physical space.

When we do the same kind of thing,

there’s a thing called the multiway causal graph,

which is the analog of a causal graph

for the multiway system.

We slice that, we get essentially the relationships

between things, not in physical space,

but in the space of quantum states.

It’s like which quantum state

is similar to which other quantum state.

Okay, so now I think next thing to say

is just to mention how quantum measurement works.

So quantum measurement has to do with reference frames

in branchial space.

So, okay, so measurement in physical space,

it matters whether how we assign spatial position

and how we define coordinates in space and time.

And that’s how we make measurements in ordinary space.

Are we making a measurement based on us sitting still here?

Are we traveling at half the speed of light

and making measurements that way?

These are different reference frames

in which we’re making our measurements.

And the relationship between different events

and different points in space and time

will be different depending on what reference frame we’re in.

Okay, so then we have this idea

of quantum observation frames,

which are the analog of reference frames,

but in branchial space.

And so what happens is what we realize

is that a quantum measurement is the observer

is sort of arbitrarily determining this reference frame.

The observer is saying, I’m going to understand the world

by saying that space and time are coordinated this way.

I’m gonna understand the world by saying

that quantum states and time are coordinated in this way.

And essentially what happens is

that the process of quantum measurement

is a process of deciding how you slice up

this multiway system in these quantum observation frames.

So in a sense, the observer, the way the observer enters

is by their choice of these quantum observation frames.

And what happens is that the observer,

because, okay, this is again,

another stack of other concepts, but anyway,

because the observer is computationally bounded,

there is a limit to the type of quantum observation frames

that they can construct.

Interesting, okay, so there’s some constraints,

some limit on the choice of observation frames.

Right, and by the way, I just want to mention

that there’s a, I mean, it’s bizarre,

but there’s a hierarchy of these things.

So in thermodynamics,

the fact that we believe entropy increases,

we believe things get more disordered,

is a consequence of the fact

that we can’t track each individual molecule.

If we could track every single molecule,

we could run every movie in reverse, so to speak,

and we would not see that things are getting more disordered.

But it’s because we are computationally bounded,

we can only look at these big blobs

of what all these molecules collectively do,

that we think that things are,

that we describe it in terms of entropy increasing

and so on.

And it’s the same phenomenon, basically,

and also a consequence of computational irreducibility

that causes us to basically be forced to conclude

that definite things happen in the world,

even though there’s this quantum,

this set of all these different quantum processes

that are going on.

So, I mean, I’m skipping a little bit,

but that’s a rough picture.

And in the evolution of the Wolfram Physics Project,

where do you feel we stand on some of the puzzles

that are along the way?

See, you’re skipping along a bunch of stuff.

It’s amazing how much these things are unraveling.

I mean, you know, these things, look,

it used to be the case that I would agree with Dick Feynman,

nobody understands quantum mechanics, including me, okay?

I’m getting to the point where I think

I actually understand quantum mechanics.

My exercise, okay, is can I explain quantum mechanics

for real at the level of kind of middle school

type explanation?

And I’m getting closer, it’s getting there.

I’m not quite there, I’ve tried it a few times,

and I realized that there are things

where I have to start talking about

elaborate mathematical concepts and so on.

But I think, and you’ve got to realize

that it’s not self evident that we can explain

at an intuitively graspable level,

something which, about the way the universe works,

the universe wasn’t built for our understanding,

so to speak.

But I think then, okay, so another important idea

is this idea of branchial space, which I mentioned,

this sort of space of quantum states.

It is, okay, so I mentioned Einstein’s equations

describing the effect of mass and energy

on trajectories of particles, on GD6.

The curvature of physical space is associated

with the presence of energy,

according to Einstein’s equations, okay?

So it turns out that, rather amazingly,

the same thing is true in branchial space.

So it turns out the presence of energy

or more accurately Lagrangian density,

which is a kind of relativistic invariant version of energy,

the presence of that causes essentially deflection of GD6

in this branchial space, okay?

So you might say, so what?

Well, it turns out that the sort of the best formulation

we have of quantum mechanics,

this Feynman path integral,

is a thing that describes quantum processes

in terms of mathematics that can be interpreted as,

well, in quantum mechanics, the big thing

is you get these quantum amplitudes,

which are complex numbers that represent,

when you combine them together,

represent probabilities of things happening.

And so the big story has been,

how do you derive these quantum amplitudes?

And people think these quantum amplitudes,

they have a complex number,

has a real part and an imaginary part.

You can also think of it as a magnitude and a phase.

And people have sort of thought these quantum amplitudes

have magnitude and phase, and you compute those together.

Turns out that the magnitude and the phase

come from completely different places.

The magnitude comes, okay, so how do you compute things

in quantum mechanics?

Roughly, I’m telling you, I’m getting there

to be able to do this at a middle school level,

but I’m not there yet.

Roughly what happens is you’re asking,

does this state in quantum mechanics

evolve to this other state in quantum mechanics?

And you can think about that like a particle traveling

or something traveling through physical space,

but instead it’s traveling through branchial space.

And so what’s happening is, does this quantum state evolve

to this other quantum state?

It’s like saying, does this object move

from this place in space to this other place in space?

Okay, now the way that these quantum amplitudes

characterize kind of to what extent the thing

will successfully reach some particular point

in branchial space, just like in physical space,

you could say, oh, it had a certain velocity

and it went in this direction.

In branchial space, there’s a similar kind of concept.

Is there a nice way to visualize for me now

mentally branchial space?

It’s just, you have this hypergraph,

sorry, you have this multiway graph.

It’s this big branching thing, branching and merging thing.

But I mean, like moving through that space,

I’m just trying to understand what that looks like.

You know, that space is probably exponential dimensional,

which makes it again, another can of worms

in understanding what’s going on.

That space as in an ordinary space,

this hypergraph, the spatial hypergraph

limits to something which is like a manifold,

like something like three dimensional space.

Almost certainly the multiway graph limits

to a Hilbert space, which is something that,

I mean, it’s just a weird exponential dimensional space.

And by the way, you can ask, I mean,

there are much weirder things that go on.

For example, one of the things I’ve been interested in

is the expansion of the universe in branchial space.

So we know the universe is expanding in physical space,

but the universe is probably also expanding

in branchial space.

So that means the number of quantum states

of the universe is increasing with time.

The diameter of the thing is growing.

Right, so that means that the,

and by the way, this is related

to whether quantum computing can ever work.

Why?

Okay, so let me explain why.

So let’s talk about, okay, so first of all,

just to finish the thought about quantum amplitudes,

that the incredibly beautiful thing,

but I’m just very excited about this.

The fine path integral is this formula.

It says that the amplitude, the quantum amplitude

is E to the I S over H bar,

where S is the thing called the action.

And it, okay, so that can be thought of

as representing a deflection of the angle

of this path in the multiway graph.

So it’s a deflection of a geodesic in the multiway path

that is caused by this thing called the action,

which is essentially associated with energy, okay?

And so this is a deflection of a path in branchial space

that is described by this path integral,

which is the thing that is the mathematical essence

of quantum mechanics.

Turns out that deflection is,

the deflection of geodesics in branchial space

follows the exact same mathematical setup

as the deflection of geodesics in physical space,

except the deflection of geodesics in physical space

is described with Einstein’s equations.

The deflection of geodesics in branchial space

is defined by the Feynman path integral,

and they are the same.

In other words, they are mathematically the same.

So that means that general relativity

is a story of essentially motion in physical space.

Quantum mechanics is a story of essentially motion

in branchial space.

And the underlying equation for those two things,

although it’s presented differently

because one’s interested in different things

in branchial space than physical space,

but the underlying equation is the same.

So in other words, it’s just these two theories,

which are those two sort of pillars

of 20th century physics,

which have seemed to be off in different directions,

are actually facets of the exact same theory.

That’s exciting to see where that evolves

and exciting that that just is there.

Right, I mean, to me,

look, having spent some part of my early life

working in the context of these theories

of 20th century physics,

it’s, they just, they seem so different.

And the fact that they’re really the same

is just really amazing.

Actually, you mentioned double slit experiment, okay?

So the double slit experiment

is an interference phenomenon where you say there are,

you can have a photon or an electron,

and you say there are these two slits

that could have gone through either one,

but there is this interference pattern

where there’s destructive interference,

where you might’ve said in classical physics,

oh, well, if there are two slits,

then there’s a better chance

that it gets through one or the other of them.

But in quantum mechanics,

there’s this phenomenon of destructive interference

that means that even though there are two slits,

two can lead to nothing,

as opposed to two leading to more

than, for example, one slit.

And what happens in this model,

and we’ve just been understanding this

in the last few weeks, actually,

is that what essentially happens

is that the double slit experiment

is a story of the interface

between branchial space and physical space.

And what’s essentially happening

is that the destructive interference

is the result of the two possible paths

associated with photons going through those two slits

winding up at opposite ends of branchial space.

And so that’s why there’s sort of nothing there

when you look at it,

is because these two different sort of branches

couldn’t get merged together

to produce something that you can measure

in physical space.

Is there a lot to be understood about branchial space?

I guess, mathematically speaking.

Yes, it’s a very beautiful mathematical thing.

And it’s very, I mean, by the way,

this whole theory is just amazingly rich

in terms of the mathematics that it says should exist.

Okay, so for example,

calculus is a story of infinitesimal change

in integer dimensional space,

one dimensional, two dimensional, three dimensional space.

We need a theory of infinitesimal change

in fractional dimensional and dynamic dimensional space.

No such theory exists.

So there’s tools of mathematics that are needed here.

Right.

And this is a motivation for that actually.

Right, and there are indications

and we can do computer experiments

and we can see how it’s gonna come out,

but we need to, the actual mathematics doesn’t exist.

And in branchial space, it’s actually even worse.

There’s even more sort of layers of mathematics that are,

we can see how it works roughly

by doing computer experiments,

but to really understand it,

we need more sort of mathematical sophistication.

So quantum computers.

Okay, so the basic idea of quantum computers,

the promise of quantum computers

is quantum mechanics does things in parallel.

And so you can sort of intrinsically do computations

in parallel.

And somehow that can be much more efficient

than just doing them one after another.

And I actually worked on quantum computing a bit

with Dick Feynman back in 1981, two, three,

that kind of timeframe.

And we…

It’s a fascinating image.

You and Feynman working on quantum computers.

Well, we tried to work,

the big thing we tried to do was invent a randomness chip

that would generate randomness at a high speed

using quantum mechanics.

And the discovery that that wasn’t really possible

was part of the story of,

we never really wrote anything about it.

I think maybe he wrote some stuff,

but we didn’t write stuff about what we figured out

about sort of the fact that it really seemed like

the measurement process in quantum mechanics

was a serious damper on what was possible to do

in sort of the possible advantages of quantum mechanics

for computing.

But anyway, so the sort of the promise of quantum computing

is let’s say you’re trying to factor an integer.

Well, you can, instead of,

when you factor an integer, you might say,

well, does this factor work?

Does this factor work?

In ordinary computing,

it seems like we pretty much just have to try

all these different factors,

kind of one after another.

But in quantum mechanics, you might have the idea,

oh, you can just sort of have the physics,

try all of them in parallel, okay?

And there’s this algorithm, Shor’s algorithm,

which allows you,

according to the formalism of quantum mechanics,

to do everything in parallel

and to do it much faster than you can on a classical computer.

Okay, the only little footnote is

you have to figure out what the answer is.

You have to measure the result.

So the quantum mechanics internally has figured out

all these different branches,

but then you have to pull all these branches together

to say, and the classical answer is this, okay?

The standard theory of quantum mechanics

does not tell you how to do that.

It tells you how the branching works,

but it doesn’t tell you the process

of corralling all these things together.

And that process, which intuitively you can see

is gonna be kind of tricky,

but our model actually does tell you

how that process of pulling things together works.

And the answer seems to be, we’re not absolutely sure.

We’ve only got to two times three so far

which is kind of in this factorization

in quantum computers.

But we can, what seems to be the case

is that the advantage you get from the parallelization

from quantum mechanics is lost

from the amount that you have to spend

pulling together all those parallel threads

to get to a classical answer at the end.

Now, that phenomenon is not unrelated

to various decoherence phenomena

that are seen in practical quantum computers and so on.

I mean, I should say as a very practical point,

I mean, it’s like, should people stop bothering

to do quantum computing research?

No, because what they’re really doing

is they’re trying to use physics

to get to a new level of what’s possible in computing.

And that’s a completely valid activity.

Whether you can really put, you know,

whether you can say,

oh, you can solve an NP complete problem.

You can reduce exponential time to polynomial time.

You know, we’re not sure.

And I’m suspecting the answer is no,

but that’s not relevant to the practical speed ups

you can get by using different kinds of technologies,

different kinds of physics to do basic computing.

But you’re saying, I mean,

some of the models you’re playing with,

the indication is that to get all the sheep back together

and, you know, to corral everything together,

to get the actual solution to the algorithm is…

You lose all the…

You lose all of the…

By the way, I mean, so again, this question,

do we actually know what we’re talking about

about quantum computing and so on?

So again, we’re doing proof by compilation.

So we have a quantum computing framework

in Wolfram language,

and which is, you know,

a standard quantum computing framework

that represents things in terms of the standard,

you know, formalism of quantum mechanics.

And we have a compiler that simply compiles

the representation of quantum gates into multiway systems.

So, and in fact, the message that I got

was from somebody who’s working on the project

who has managed to compile one of the sort of

a core formalism based on category theory

and core quantum formalism into multiway systems.

So this is…

When you say multiway system, these multiway graphs?

Yes.

So you’re compiling…

Yeah, okay, that’s awesome.

And then you can do all kinds of experiments

on that multiway graph.

Right, but the point is that what we’re saying is

the thing we’ve got this representation

of let’s say Shor’s algorithm

in terms of standard quantum gates.

And it’s just a pure matter of sort of computation

to just say that is equivalent.

We will get the same result as running this multiway system.

Can you do complexity analysis on that multiway system?

Well, that’s what we’ve been trying to do, yes.

We’re getting there.

We haven’t done that yet.

I mean, there’s a pretty good indication

of how that’s gonna work out.

We’ve done, as I say, our computer experiments.

We’ve unimpressively gotten to about two times three

in terms of factorization,

which is kind of about how far people have got

with physical quantum computers as well.

But yes, we will be able to do…

We definitely will be able to do complexity analysis

and we will be able to know.

So the one remaining hope for quantum computing

really, really working at this formal level

of quantum brand exponential stuff being done

in polynomial time and so on.

The one hope, which is very bizarre,

is that you can kind of piggyback

on the expansion of branchial space.

So here’s how that might work.

So you think, you know, energy conservation,

standard thing in high school physics,

energy is conserved, right?

But now you imagine, you think about energy

in the context of cosmology

and the context of the whole universe.

It’s a much more complicated story.

The expansion of the universe kind of violates

energy conservation.

And so for example, if you imagine you’ve got two galaxies,

they’re receding from each other very quickly.

They’ve got two big central black holes.

You connect a spring between these two central black holes.

Not easy to do in practice,

but let’s imagine you could do it.

Now that spring is being pulled apart.

It’s getting more potential energy in the spring

as a result of the expansion of the universe.

So in a sense, you are piggybacking on the expansion

that exists in the universe

and the sort of violation of energy conservation

that’s associated with that cosmological expansion

to essentially get energy.

You’re essentially building a perpetual motion machine

by using the expansion of the universe.

And that is a physical version of that.

It is conceivable that the same thing can be done

in branchial space to essentially mine the expansion

of the universe in branchial space

as a way to get sort of quantum computing for free,

so to speak, just from the expansion of the universe

in branchial space.

Now, the physical space version is kind of absurd

and involves springs between black holes and so on.

It’s conceivable that the branchial space version

is not as absurd

and that it’s actually something you can reach

with physical things you can build in labs and so on.

We don’t know yet.

Okay, so like you were saying,

the branch of space might be expanding

and there might be something that could be exploited.

Right, in the same kind of way

that you can exploit that expansion of the universe

in principle, in physical space.

You just have like a glimmer of hope.

Right, I think that the,

look, I think the real answer is going to be

that for practical purposes,

the official brand that says you can do exponential things

in polynomial time is probably not gonna work.

For people curious to kind of learn more,

so this is more like, it’s not middle school,

we’re gonna go to elementary school for a second.

Maybe middle school, let’s go to middle school.

So if I were to try to maybe write a pamphlet

of like Wolfram physics project for dummies,

AKA for me, or maybe make a video on the basics,

but not just the basics of the physics project,

but the basics plus the most beautiful central ideas.

How would you go about doing that?

Could you help me out a little bit?

Yeah, yeah, I mean, as a really practical matter,

we have this kind of visual summary picture that we made,

which I think is a pretty good,

when I’ve tried to explain this to people

and it’s a pretty good place to start.

As you got this rule, you apply the rule,

you’re building up this big hypergraph,

you’ve got all these possibilities,

you’re kind of thinking about that

in terms of quantum mechanics.

I mean, that’s a decent place to start.

So basically the things we’ve talked about,

which is space represented as a hypergraph,

transformation of that space is kind of time.

Yes.

And then…

Structure of that space,

the curvature of that space has gravity.

That can be explained without going anywhere

near quantum mechanics.

I would say that’s actually easier to explain

than special relativity.

Oh, so going into general, so go into curvature.

Yeah, I mean, special relativity,

I think it’s a little bit elaborate to explain.

And honestly, you only care about it

if you know about special relativity,

if you know how special relativity

is ordinarily derived and so on.

So general relativity is easier.

Is easier, yes.

And then what about quantum?

What’s the easiest way to reveal…

I think the basic point is just this.

This fact that there are all these different branches,

that there’s this kind of map of how the branches work.

And that, I mean, I think actually the recent things

that we have about the double slit experiment

are pretty good, because you can actually see this.

You can see how the double slit phenomenon arises

from just features of these graphs.

Now, having said that,

there is a little bit of sleight of hand there

because the true story of the way

that double slit thing works

depends on the coordination of branchial space

that, for example, in our internal team,

there is still a vigorous battle going on

about how that works.

And what’s becoming clear is…

I mean, what’s becoming clear

is that it’s mathematically really quite interesting.

I mean, that is that there’s a…

It involves essentially putting space filling curves.

You’ll basically have a thing

which is naturally two dimensional,

and you’re sort of mapping it into one dimension

with a space filling curve.

And it’s like, why is it this space filling curve

and another space filling curve?

And that becomes a story about Riemann surfaces and things,

and it’s quite elaborate.

But there’s a more, a little bit sleight of hand way

of doing it where it’s surprisingly direct.

It’s…

So a question that might be difficult to answer,

but for several levels of people,

could you give me advice on how we can learn more?

Specifically, there is people that are completely outside

and just curious and are captivated

by the beauty of hypergraphs, actually.

So people that just wanna explore, play around with this.

Second level is people from, say, people like me

who somehow got a PhD in computer science,

but are not physicists.

But fundamentally, the work you’re doing

is of computational nature.

So it feels very accessible.

So what can a person like that do to learn enough physics

or not to be able to, one, explore the beauty of it,

and two, the final level of contribute something

of a level of even publishable,

like strong, interesting ideas.

So at all those layers, complete beginner,

a CS person, and the CS person that wants to publish.

I mean, I think that, I’ve written a bunch of stuff,

a person called Jonathan Gorod,

who’s been a key person working on this project,

has also written a bunch of stuff.

And some other people started writing things too.

And he’s a physicist.

Physicist.

Well, he’s, I would say, a mathematical physicist.

Mathematical.

Mathematical physicist.

He’s pretty mathematically sophisticated.

He regularly outmathematicizes me.

Yeah, strong mathematical physicist.

Yeah, I looked at some of the papers.

Right, but so, I mean,

I wrote this kind of original announcement blog post

about this project, which people seem to have found.

I’ve been really happy, actually, that people who,

people seem to have grokked key points from that,

much deeper key points, people seem to have grokked

than I thought they would grokk.

And that’s a kind of a long blog post

that explains some of the things we talked about,

like the hypergraph and the basic rules.

And I don’t, does it, I forget,

it doesn’t have any quantum mechanics in here.

It does. It does.

But we know a little bit more since that blog post

that probably clarifies,

but that blog post does a pretty decent job.

And, you know, talking about things like, again,

something we didn’t mention,

the fact that the uncertainty principle

is a consequence of curvature in branchial space.

How much physics should a person know

to be able to understand the beauty of this framework

and to contribute something novel?

Okay, so I think that those are different questions.

So, I mean, I think that the, why does this work?

Why does this make any sense?

To really know that,

you have to know a fair amount of physics, okay?

And for example, have a decent understanding.

When you say, why does this work?

You’re referring to the connection between this model

and general relativity, for example.

You have to understand something about general relativity.

There’s also a side of this where just

as the pure mathematical framework is fascinating.

Yes.

If you throw the physics out completely.

Then it’s quite accessible to, I mean, you know,

I wrote this sort of long technical introduction

to the project, which seems to have been very accessible

to people who are, you know, who understand computation

and formal abstract ideas, but are not specialists

in physics or other kinds of things.

I mean, the thing with the physics part of it is,

you know, there’s both a way of thinking

and literally a mathematical formalism.

I mean, it’s like, you know,

to know that we get the Einstein equations,

to know we get the energy momentum tensor,

you kind of have to know what the energy momentum tensor is.

And that’s physics.

I mean, that’s kind of graduate level physics basically.

And so that, you know, making that final connection

is requires some depth of physics knowledge.

I mean, that’s the unfortunate thing,

the difference in machine learning and physics

in the 21st century.

Is it really out of reach of a year or two worth of study?

No, you could get it in a year or two,

but you can’t get it in a month.

Right.

I mean.

So, but it doesn’t require necessarily like 15 years.

No, it does not.

And in fact, a lot of what has happened with this project

makes a lot of this stuff much more accessible.

There are things where it has been quite difficult

to explain what’s going on.

And it requires much more, you know,

having the concreteness of being able to do simulations,

knowing that this thing that you might’ve thought

was just an analogy is really actually what’s going on,

makes one feel much more secure

about just sort of saying, this is how this works.

And I think it will be, you know,

the, I’m hoping the textbooks of the future,

the physics textbooks of the future,

there will be a certain compression.

There will be things that used to be

very much more elaborate because for example,

even doing continuous mathematics

versus this discrete mathematics,

that, you know, to know how things work

in continuous mathematics,

you have to be talking about stuff

and waving your hands about things.

Whereas with discrete, the discrete version,

it’s just like, here is a picture.

This is how it works.

And there’s no, oh, do we get the limit right?

Did this, you know, did this thing that is of,

you know, zero, you know, measure zero object,

you know, interact with this thing in the right way.

You don’t have to have that whole discussion.

It’s just like, here’s a picture, you know,

this is what it does.

And, you know, you can, then it takes more effort to say,

what does it do in the limit when the picture gets very big?

But you can do experiments

to build up an intuition actually.

Yes, right.

And you can get sort of core intuition for what’s going on.

Now, in terms of contributing to this, the, you know,

I would say that the study of the computational universe

and how all these programs work

in the computational universe,

there’s just an unbelievable amount to do there.

And it is very close to the surface.

That is, you know, high school kids,

you can do experiments.

It’s not, you know, and you can discover things.

I mean, you know, we, you can discover stuff about,

I don’t know, like this thing about expansion

of branchial space.

That’s an absolutely accessible thing to look at.

Now, you know, the main issue with doing these things

is not, there isn’t a lot of technical depth difficulty

there.

The actual doing of the experiments, you know,

all the code is all on our website to do all these things.

The real thing is sort of the judgment

of what’s the right experiment to do.

How do you interpret what you see?

That’s the part that, you know,

people will do amazing things with.

And that’s the part that, but,

but it isn’t like you have to have done 10 years of study

to get to the point where you can do the experiments.

You don’t.

That’s a cool thing you can do experiments day one,

basically.

That’s the amazing thing about,

and you’ve actually put the tools out there.

It’s beautiful.

It’s mysterious.

There’s still, I would say, maybe you can correct me.

It feels like there’s a huge number of log hanging fruit

on the mathematical side, at least not the physics side,

perhaps.

No, there’s, look on the, on the, okay.

On the physics side, we are,

we’re definitely in harvesting mode, you know.

Of which, which fruit, the low hanging ones or?

The low hanging ones, yeah, right.

I mean, basically here’s the thing.

There’s a certain list of, you know,

here are the effects in quantum mechanics.

Here are the effects in general activity.

It’s just like industrial harvesting.

It’s like, can we get this one, this one, this one,

this one, this one?

And the thing that’s really, you know,

interesting and satisfying, and it’s like, you know,

is one climbing the right mountain?

Does one have the right model?

The thing that’s just amazing is, you know,

we keep on like, are we going to get this one?

How hard is this one?

It’s like, oh, you know, it looks really hard.

It looks really hard.

Oh, actually we can get it.

And.

And you’re, you’re continually surprised.

I mean, it seems like I’ve been following your progress.

It’s kind of exciting.

All the, in harvesting mode,

all the things you’re picking up along the way.

Right, right.

No, I mean, it’s, it’s the thing that is,

I keep on thinking it’s going to be more difficult

than it is.

Now that’s a, you know, that’s a, who knows what,

I mean, the one thing, so the, the, the,

the thing that’s been a, was a big thing

that I think we’re, we’re pretty close to.

I mean, I can give you a little bit of the roadmap.

It’s sort of interesting to see, it’s like,

what are particles?

What are things like electrons?

How do they really work?

Are you close to get like, what, what’s a,

are you close to trying to understand like the atom,

the electrons, neutrons, protons?

Okay, so this is, this is the stack.

So the first thing we want to understand is

the quantization of spin.

So particles, they, they kind of spin,

they have a certain angular momentum,

that angular momentum,

even though the masses of particles are all over the place,

you know, the electron has a mass of 0.511 MeV,

but you know, the proton is 938 MeV, et cetera, et cetera,

et cetera, they’re all kind of random numbers.

The, the spins of all these particles

are either integers or half integers.

And that’s a fact that was discovered in the 1920s, I guess.

The, I think that we are close to understanding

why spin is quantized.

And that’s a, and it, it appears to be

a quite elaborate mathematical story

about homotopic groups in twister space

and all kinds of things.

But bottom line is that seems within reach.

And that’s, that’s a big deal

because that’s a very core feature of understanding

how particles work in quantum mechanics.

Another core feature is this difference between particles

that obey the exclusion principle and sort of stay apart,

that leads to the stability of matter and things like that,

and particles that love to get together

and be in the same state, things like photons,

that, and that’s what leads to phenomena like lasers,

where you can get sort of coherently

everything in the same state.

That difference is the particles of integer spin

are bosons like to get together in the same state,

the particles of half integer spin are fermions,

like electrons that they tend to stay apart.

And so the question is, can we get that in our models?

And, oh, just the last few days, I think we made,

I mean, I think the story of,

I mean, it’s one of these things where we’re really close.

Is this connected fermions and bosons?

Yeah, yeah.

So this was what happens is what seems to happen, okay?

It’s, you know, subject to revision in the next few days.

But what seems to be the case is that

bosons are associated with essentially

merging in multiway graphs,

and fermions are associated with branching

in multiway graphs.

And that essentially the exclusion principle

is the fact that in branchial space,

things have a certain extent in branchial space

that in which things are being sort of forced apart

in branchial space, whereas the case of bosons,

they get, they come together in branchial space.

And the real question is, can we explain the relationship

between that and these things called spinners,

which are the representation of half integer spin particles

that have this weird feature that usually when you go

around 360 degree rotation,

you get back to where you started from.

But for a spinner, you don’t get back

to where you started from.

It takes 720 degrees of rotation to get back

to where you started from.

And we are just, it feels like we are,

we’re just incredibly close to actually having that,

understanding how that works.

And it turns out, it looks like,

my current speculation is that it’s as simple

as the directed hypergraphs versus undirected hypergraphs,

the relationship between spinners and vectors.

So, which is just interesting.

Yeah, that would be interesting if these are all these kind

of nice properties of this multi way graphs of branching

and rejoining.

Spinners have been very mysterious.

And if that’s what they turn out to be,

there’s going to be an easy explanation

of what’s going on.

Directive versus undirective.

It’s just, and that’s why there’s only two different cases.

It’s why are spinners important in quantum mechanics?

Can you just give a…

Yeah, so spinners are important because they are,

they’re the representation of electrons

which have half an inch of spin.

They are, the wave functions of electrons are spinners.

Just like the wave functions of photons are vectors,

the wave functions of electrons are spinners.

And they have this property that when you rotate

by 360 degrees, they come back to minus one of themselves

and take 720 degrees to get back to the original value.

And they are a consequence of,

we usually think of rotation in space as being,

when you have this notion of rotational invariance

and rotational invariance, as we ordinarily experience it,

doesn’t have the feature.

If you go through 360 degrees,

you go back to where you started from,

but that’s not true for electrons.

And so that’s why understanding how that works is important.

Yeah, I’ve been playing with Mobius Strip

quite a bit lately, just for fun.

Yes, yes.

It adds some funk, it has the same kind of funky properties.

Yes, right, exactly.

You can have this so called belt trick,

which is this way of taking an extended object

and you can see properties like spinners

with that kind of extended object that…

Yeah, it would be very cool if there’s,

it somehow connects the directive versus undirective.

I think that’s what it’s gonna be.

I think it’s gonna be as simple as that, but we’ll see.

I mean, this is the thing that,

this is the big sort of bizarre surprise is that,

because I learned physics as probably, let’s say,

let’s say a fifth generation in the sense that,

if you go back to the 1920s and so on,

there were the people who were originating

quantum mechanics and so on.

Maybe it’s a little less than that.

Maybe I was like a third generation or something.

I don’t know, but the people from whom I learned physics

were the people who had been students of the students

of the people who originated

the current understanding of physics.

And we’re now at probably the seventh generation

of physicists or something

from the early days of 20th century physics.

And whenever a field gets that many generations deep,

it seems the foundations seem quite inaccessible.

And they seem, it seems like

you can’t possibly understand that.

We’ve gone through seven academic generations

and that’s been, you know, that’s been this thing

that’s been difficult to understand for that long.

It just can’t be that simple.

But in a sense, maybe that journey takes you

to a simple explanation that was there all along.

That’s the whole. Right, right, right.

I mean, you know, and the thing for me personally,

the thing that’s been quite interesting is, you know,

I didn’t expect this project to work in this way.

And I, you know, but I had this sort of weird piece

of personal history that I used to be a physicist

and I used to do all this stuff.

And I know, you know, the standard canon of physics,

I knew it very well.

And, you know, but then I’d been working

on this kind of computational paradigm

for basically 40 years.

And the fact that, you know, I’m sort of now coming back

to, you know, trying to apply that in physics,

it kind of felt like that journey was necessary.

Was this, when did you first try to play with a hypergraph?

So what happened is,

yeah, so what I had was, okay, so this is again,

you know, one always feels dumb after the fact.

It’s obvious after the fact.

But so back in the early 1990s,

I realized that using graphs

as a sort of underlying thing underneath space and time

was going to be a useful thing to do.

I figured out about multiway systems.

I figured out the things about general relativity

I’d figured out by the end of the 1990s.

But I always felt there was a certain inelegance

because I was using these graphs

and there were certain constraints on these graphs

that seemed like they were kind of awkward.

It was kind of like, you can pick,

it’s like you couldn’t pick any rule.

It was like pick any number, but the number has to be prime.

It was kind of like you couldn’t,

it was kind of an awkward special constraint.

I had these trivalent graphs,

graphs with just three connections from every node.

Okay, so, but I discovered a bunch of stuff with that.

And I thought it was kind of inelegant.

And, you know, the other piece of sort of personal history

is obviously I spent my life

as a computational language designer.

And so the story of computational language design

is a story of how do you take all these random ideas

in the world and kind of grind them down

into something that is computationally

as simple as possible.

And so, you know, I’ve been very interested

in kind of simple computational frameworks

for representing things and have, you know,

ridiculous amounts of experience in trying to do that.

And actually all of those trajectories of your life

kind of came together.

So you make it sound like you could have come up

with everything you’re working on now decades ago,

but in reality.

Look, two things slowed me down.

I mean, one thing that slowed me down was

I couldn’t figure out how to make it elegant.

And that turns out hypergraphs were the key to that.

And that I figured out about less than two years ago now.

And the other, I mean, I think,

so that was sort of a key thing.

Well, okay, so the real embarrassment of this project, okay,

is that the final structure that we have

that is the foundation for this project

is basically a kind of an idealized version,

a formalized version of the exact same structure

that I’ve used to build computational languages

for more than 40 years.

But it took me, but I didn’t realize that.

And, you know.

And there yet may be others.

So we’re focused on physics now,

but I mean, that’s what the new kind of science was about.

Same kind of stuff.

And this, in terms of mathematically,

well, the beauty of it.

So there could be entire other kind of objects

that are useful for,

like we’re not talking about, you know,

machine learning, for example.

Maybe there’s other variants of the hypergraph

that are very useful for reasoning.

Well, we’ll see whether the multiway graph

or machine learning system is interesting.

Okay.

Let’s leave it at that.

That’s conversation number three.

That’s, we’re not gonna go there right now, but.

One of the things you’ve mentioned

is the space of all possible rules

that we kind of discussed a little bit.

That, you know, that could be, I guess,

the set of possible rules is infinite.

Right.

Well, so here’s the big sort of one of the conundrums

that I’m kind of trying to deal with is,

let’s say we think we found the rule for the universe

and we say, here it is.

You know, write it down.

It’s a little tiny thing.

And then we say, gosh, that’s really weird.

Why did we get that one?

Right.

And then we’re in this whole situation

because let’s say it’s fairly simple.

How did we come up the winners

getting one of the simple possible universe rules?

Why didn’t we get what some incredibly complicated rule?

Why do we get one of the simpler ones?

And that’s a thing which, you know,

in the history of science, you know,

the whole sort of story of Copernicus and so on was,

you know, we used to think the earth

was the center of the universe,

but now we find out it’s not.

And we’re actually just in some, you know,

random corner of some random galaxy

out in this big universe, there’s nothing special about us.

So if we get, you know, universe number 317

out of all the infinite number of possibilities,

how do we get something that small and simple?

Right, so I was very confused by this.

And it’s like, what are we going to say about this?

How are we going to explain this?

And I thought it was, might be one of these things

where you just, you know, you can get it to the threshold,

and then you find out its rule number, such and such,

and you just have no idea why it’s like that.

Okay, so then I realized

it’s actually more bizarre than that, okay?

So we talked about multiway graphs.

We talked about this idea that

you take these underlying transformation rules

on these hypergraphs, and you apply them

wherever the rule can apply, you apply it.

And that makes this whole multiway graph of possibilities.

Okay, so let’s go a little bit weirder.

Let’s say that at every place,

not only do you apply a particular rule

in all possible ways it can apply,

but you apply all possible rules

in all possible ways they can apply.

As you say, that’s just crazy.

That’s way too complicated.

You’re never going to be able to conclude anything.

Okay, however, turns out that…

Don’t tell me there’s some kind of invariance.

Yeah, yeah.

So what happens is…

And that would be amazing.

Right, so this thing that you get

is this kind of ruleal multiway graph,

this multiway graph that is a branching of rules

as well as a branching of possible applications of rules.

This thing has causal invariance.

It’s an inevitable feature that it shows causal invariance.

And that means that you can take different reference frames,

different ways of slicing this thing,

and they will all in some sense be equivalent.

If you make the right translation, they will be equivalent.

So, okay, so the basic point here is…

If that’s true, that would be beautiful.

It is true, and it is beautiful.

It’s not just an intuition, there is some…

No, no, no, there’s real mathematics behind this,

and it is…

Okay, so here’s where it comes in.

Yeah, that’s amazing.

Right, so by the way, I mean,

the mathematics it’s connected to

is the mathematics of higher category theory

and group voids and things like this,

which I’ve always been afraid of,

but now I’m finally wrapping my arms around it.

But it’s also related to…

It also relates to computational complexity theory.

It’s also deeply related to the P versus NP problem

and other things like this.

Again, it seems completely bizarre

that these things are connected,

but here’s why it’s connected.

This space of all possible…

Okay, so a Turing machine, very simple model of computation.

You know, you just got this tape

where you write down, you know, ones and zeros

or something on the tape,

and you have this rule that says, you know,

you change the number,

you move the head on the tape, et cetera.

You have a definite rule for doing that.

A deterministic Turing machine

just does that deterministically.

Given the configuration of the tape,

it will always do the same thing.

A non deterministic Turing machine

can have different choices that it makes at every step.

And so, you know, you know this stuff,

you probably teach this stuff.

It, you know, so a non deterministic Turing machine

has the set of branching possibilities,

which is in fact, one of these multiway graphs.

And in fact, if you say,

imagine the extremely non deterministic Turing machine,

the Turing machine that can just do,

that takes any possible rule at each step,

that is this real multiway graph.

The set of possible histories

of that extreme non deterministic Turing machine

is a Rulio multiway graph.

And you’re, what term are you using?

Rulio?

Rulio.

Rulio, I like it.

It’s a weird word.

Yeah, it’s a weird word, right?

Rulio multiway graph.

Okay, so this, so that.

I’m trying to think of,

I’m trying to think of the space of rules.

So these are basic transformations.

So in a Turing machine,

it’s like it says, move left, move, you know,

if it’s a one, if it’s a black square under the head,

move left and right to green square.

That’s a rule.

That’s a very basic rule,

but I’m trying to see the rules on the hypergraphs,

how rich of the programs can they be?

Or do they all ultimately just map into something simple?

Yeah, they’re all, I mean, hypergraphs,

that’s another layer of complexity on this whole thing.

You can think about these in transformations of hypergraphs,

but Turing machines are a little bit simpler.

You just think of it Turing machines, okay.

Right, they’re a little bit simpler.

So if you look at these extreme

non deterministic Turing machines,

you’re mapping out all the possible non deterministic paths

that the Turing machine can follow.

And if you ask the question, can you reach, okay,

so a deterministic Turing machine follows a single path.

The non deterministic Turing machine fills out

this whole sort of ball of possibilities.

And so then the P versus MP problem

ends up being questions about,

and we haven’t completely figured out

all the details of this,

but it’s basically has to do with questions

about the growth of that ball relative

to what happens with individual paths and so on.

So essentially there’s a geometrization

of the P versus MP problem that comes out of this.

That’s a sideshow, okay.

The main event here is the statement

that you can look at this multiway graph

where the branches correspond

not just to different applications of a single rule,

but to different applications of different rules, okay.

And that then that when you say,

I’m going to be an observer embedded in that system

and I’m going to try and make sense

of what’s going on in the system.

And to do that, I essentially am picking a reference frame

and that turns out to be, well, okay.

So the way this comes out essentially

is the reference frame you pick

is the rule that you infer is what’s going on

in the universe, even though all possible rules

are being run, although all those possible rules

are in a sense giving the same answer

because of causal invariance.

But what you see could be completely different.

If you pick different reference frames,

you essentially have a different description language

for describing the universe.

Okay, so what does this really mean in practice?

So imagine there’s us.

We think about the universe in terms of space and time

and we have various kinds of description models and so on.

Now let’s imagine the friendly aliens, for example, right?

How do they describe their universe?

Well, you know, our description of the universe

probably is affected by the fact that, you know,

we are about the size we are, you know,

a meter ish tall, so to speak.

We have brain processing speeds,

we’re about the speeds we have.

We’re not the size of planets, for example,

where the speed of light really would matter.

You know, in our everyday life,

the speed of light doesn’t really matter.

Everything can be, you know,

the fact that the speed of light is finite is irrelevant.

It could as well be infinite.

We wouldn’t make any difference.

You know, it affects the ping times on the internet.

That’s about the level of how we notice the speed of light.

In our sort of everyday existence,

we don’t really notice it.

And so we have a way of describing the universe

that’s based on our sensory, you know, our senses,

these days also on the mathematics we’ve constructed

and so on, but the realization is

it’s not the only way to do it.

There will be completely, utterly incoherent descriptions

of the universe, which correspond

to different reference frames in this sort of ruleal space.

In the ruleal space, that’s fascinating.

So we have some kind of reference frame

in this ruleal space, and from that.

That’s why we are attributing this rule to the universe.

So in other words, when we say,

why is it this rule and not another,

the answer is just, you know,

shine the light back on us, so to speak.

It’s because of the reference frame that we’ve picked

in our way of understanding what’s happening

in this sort of space of all possible rules and so on.

But also in the space from this reference frame,

because of the ruleal, the invariance,

that simple, that the rule on which the universe,

with which you can run the universe,

might as well be simple.

Yes, yes, but okay, so here’s another point.

So this is, again, these are a little bit mind twisting

in some ways, but the, okay, another thing that’s sort of,

we know from computation is this idea

of computation universality.

The fact that given that we have a program

that runs on one kind of computer, we can as well,

you know, we can convert it to run

on any other kind of computer.

We can emulate one kind of computer with another.

So that might lead you to say, well,

you think you have the rule for the universe,

but you might as well be running it on a Turing machine

because we know we can emulate any computational rule

on any kind of machine.

And that’s essentially the same thing

that’s being said here.

That is that what we’re doing is we’re saying

these different interpretations of physics correspond

to essentially running physics

on different underlying, you know,

thinking about the physics as running in different

with different underlying rules

as if different underlying computers were running them.

And, but because of computation universality

or more accurately, because of this principle

of computational equivalence thing of mine,

there’s that they are,

these things are ultimately equivalent.

So the only thing that is the ultimate fact

about the universe, the ultimate fact that doesn’t depend

on any of these, you know, we don’t have to talk

about specific rules, et cetera, et cetera, et cetera.

The ultimate fact is the universe is computational

and it is the things that happen in the universe

are the kinds of computations that the principle

of computational equivalence says should happen.

Now that might sound like you’re not really saying

anything there, but you are because you can,

you could in principle have a hyper computer

that things that take an ordinary computer

an infinite time to do the hyper computer can just say,

oh, I know the answer.

It’s this immediately.

What this is saying is the universe is not a hyper computer.

It’s not simpler than a,

an ordinary Turing machine type computer.

It’s exactly like an ordinary Turing machine type computer.

And so that’s the, that’s in the end,

the sort of net net conclusion is that’s the thing

that is the sort of the hard immovable fact

about the universe.

That’s sort of the fundamental principle of the universe

is that it is computational and not hyper computational

and not sort of infra computational.

It is this level of computational ability

and it’s, it kind of has,

and that’s sort of the, the, the core fact, but now,

you know, this, this idea that you can have these different

kind of a rule reference frames,

these different description languages for the universe.

It makes me, you know, I used to think, okay, you know,

imagine the aliens,

imagine the extraterrestrial intelligence thing, you know,

at least they experienced the same physics.

And now I’ve realized it isn’t true.

They could have a different rule frame.

That’s fascinating.

That they can end up with a, a, a,

a description of the universe that is utterly,

utterly incoherent with ours.

And that’s also interesting in terms of how we think about,

well, intelligence, the nature of intelligence and so on.

You know, I’m, I’m fond of the quote, you know,

the weather has a mind of its own because these are,

you know, these are sort of computationally that,

that system is computationally equivalent to the system

that is our brains and so on.

And what’s different is we don’t have a way to understand,

you know, what the weather is trying to do, so to speak.

We have a story about what’s happening in our brains.

We don’t have a sort of connection

to what’s happening there.

So we actually, it’s funny,

last time we talked maybe over a year ago,

we talked about how it was more based on your work

with Arrival.

We talked about how would we communicate

with alien intelligences.

Can you maybe comment on how we might,

how the Wolfram Physics Project changed your view,

how we might be able to communicate

with alien intelligence?

Like if they showed up,

is it possible that because of our comprehension

of the physics of the world might be completely different,

we would just not be able to communicate at all?

Here’s the thing, you know, intelligence is everywhere.

The fact this idea that there’s this notion of,

oh, there’s gonna be this amazing

extraterrestrial intelligence

and it’s gonna be this unique thing.

It’s just not true.

It’s the same thing.

You know, I think people will realize this

about the time when people decide

that artificial intelligences are kind of

just natural things that are like human intelligences.

They’ll realize that extraterrestrial intelligences

or intelligences associated with physical systems

and so on, it’s all the same kind of thing.

It’s ultimately computation.

It’s all the same.

It’s all just computation.

And the issue is, can you, are you sort of inside it?

Are you thinking about it?

Do you have sort of a story you’re telling yourself

about it?

And you know, the weather could have a story

it’s telling itself about what it’s doing.

We just, it’s utterly incoherent with the stories

that we tell ourselves based on how our brains work.

I mean, ultimately it must be a question

whether we can align.

Exactly.

Align with the kind of intelligence.

Right, right, right.

So there’s a systematic way of doing it.

Right, so the question is in the space

of all possible intelligences,

what’s the, how do you think about the distance

between description languages

for one intelligence versus another?

And needless to say, I have thought about this

and you know, I don’t have a great answer yet,

but I think that’s a thing

where there will be things that can be said

and there’ll be things that where you can sort of

start to characterize, you know,

what is the translation distance between this,

you know, version of the universe

or this kind of set of computational rules

and this other one.

In fact, okay, so this is a, you know,

there’s this idea of algorithmic information theory.

There’s this question of sort of what is the,

when you have something,

what is the sort of shortest description you can make of it

where that description could be saying,

run this program to get the thing, right?

So I’m pretty sure that there will be a physicalization

of the idea of algorithmic information

and that, okay, this is again, a little bit bizarre,

but so I mentioned that there’s the speed of light,

maximum speed of information transmission in physical space.

There’s a maximum speed of information transmission

in branchial space, which is a maximum entanglement speed.

There’s a maximum speed of information transmission

in ruleal space, which is,

has to do with a maximum speed of translation

between different description languages.

And again, I’m not fully wrapped my brain around this one.

Yeah, that one just blows my mind to think about that,

but that starts getting closer to the, yeah,

the intelligence. It’s kind of a physicalization.

Right, and it’s also a physicalization

of algorithmic information.

And I think there’s probably a connection between,

I mean, there’s probably a connection

between the notion of energy and some of these things,

which again, I hadn’t seen all this coming.

I’ve always been a little bit resistant

to the idea of connecting physical energy

to things in computation theory,

but I think that’s probably coming.

And that’s what essentially at the core

with the physics project is

that you’re connecting information theory with physics.

Yeah, it’s computation.

Computation with our physical universe.

Yeah, right.

I mean, the fact that our physical universe is,

right, that we can think of it as a computation

and that we can have discussions like,

the theory of the physical universe

is the same kind of a theory as the P versus MP problem

and so on is really, I think that’s really interesting.

And the fact that, well, okay,

so this kind of brings me to one more thing

that I have to in terms of this sort of unification

of different ideas, which is metamathematics.

Yeah, let’s talk about that.

You mentioned that earlier.

What the heck is metamathematics and…

Okay, so here’s what, okay.

So what is mathematics?

Mathematics, sort of at a lowest level,

one thinks of mathematics as you have certain axioms.

You say things like X plus Y is the same as Y plus X.

That’s an axiom about addition.

And then you say, we’ve got these axioms

and from these axioms, we derive all these theorems

that fill up the literature of mathematics.

The activity of mathematicians

is to derive all these theorems.

Actually, the axioms of mathematics are very small.

You can fit, when I did my new kind of science book,

I fit all of the standard axioms of mathematics

on basically a page and a half.

Not much stuff.

It’s like a very simple rule

from which all of mathematics arises.

The way it works though is a little different

from the way things work in sort of a computation

because in mathematics, what you’re interested in

is a proof and the proof says,

from here, you can use, from this expression, for example,

you can use these axioms to get to this other expression.

So that proves these two things are equal.

Okay, so we can begin to see how this has been going to work.

What’s gonna happen is there are paths

in metamathematical space.

So what happens is each, two different ways to look at it.

You can just look at it as mathematical expressions

or you can look at it as mathematical statements,

postulates or something.

But either way, you think of these things

and they are connected by these axioms.

So in other words, you have some fact

or you have some expression, you apply this axiom,

you get some other expression.

And in general, given some expression,

there may be many possible different expressions

you can get.

You basically build up a multiway graph

and a proof is a path through the multiway graph

that goes from one thing to another thing.

The path tells you how did you get from one thing

to the other thing.

It’s the story of how you got from this to that.

The theorem is the thing at one end

is equal to the thing at the other end.

The proof is the path you go down

to get from one thing to the other.

You mentioned that Gödel’s incompleteness theorem

fits naturally there.

How does it fit?

Yeah, so what happens there is that the Gödel’s theorem

is basically saying that there are paths of infinite length.

That is that there’s no upper bound.

If you know these two things,

you say, I’m trying to get from here to here,

how long do I have to go?

You say, well, I’ve looked at all the paths of length 10.

Somebody says, that’s not good enough.

That path might be of length a billion.

And there’s no upper bound on how long that path is.

And that’s what leads to the incompleteness theorem.

So I mean, the thing that is kind of an emerging idea

is you can start asking,

what’s the analog of Einstein’s equations

in metamathematical space?

What’s the analog of a black hole

in metamathematical space?

What’s the hope of this?

So yeah, it’s fascinating to model all the mathematics

in this way.

So here’s what it is.

This is mathematics in bulk.

So human mathematicians have made a few million theorems.

They’ve published a few million theorems.

But imagine the infinite future of mathematics.

Apply something to mathematics

that mathematics likes to apply to other things.

Take a limit.

What is the limit of the infinite future of mathematics?

What does it look like?

What is the continuum limit of mathematics?

What is the, as you just fill in

more and more and more theorems,

what does it look like?

What does it do?

How does, what kinds of conclusions can you make?

So for example, one thing I’ve just been doing

is taking Euclid.

So Euclid, very impressive.

He had 10 axioms, he derived 465 theorems, okay?

His book, you know,

that was the sort of defining book of mathematics

for 2000 years.

So you can actually map out,

and I actually did this 20 years ago,

but I’ve done it more seriously now.

You can map out the theorem dependency

of those 465 theorems.

So from the axioms, you grow this graph,

it’s actually a multiway graph,

of how all these theorems get proved from other theorems.

And so you can ask questions about, you know,

well, you can ask things like,

what’s the hardest theorem in Euclid?

The answer is, the hardest theorem

is that there are five platonic solids.

That turns out to be the hardest theorem in Euclid.

That’s actually his last theorem in all his books.

That’s the final.

What’s the hardness, the distance you have to travel?

Yeah, let’s say it’s 33 steps from the,

the longest path in the graph is 33 steps.

So that’s the, there’s a 33 step path you have to follow

to go from the axioms, according to Euclid’s proofs,

to the statement there are five platonic solids.

So, okay, so then the question is,

in, what does it mean if you have this map?

Okay, so in a sense, this metamathematical space

is the infrastructural space of all possible theorems

that you could prove in mathematics.

That’s the geometry of metamathematics.

There’s also the geography of mathematics.

That is, where did people choose to live in space?

And that’s what, for example,

exploring the sort of empirical metamathematics

that Euclid is doing.

You could put each individual, like, human mathematician,

you can embed them into that space.

I mean, they kind of live.

They represent a path in the space.

The little path.

The things they do.

Maybe a set of paths.

Right.

So like a set of axioms that are chosen.

Right, so for example,

here’s an example of a thing that I realized.

So one of the surprising things about,

well, there are two surprising facts about math.

One is that it’s hard,

and the other is that it’s doable, okay?

So first question is, why is math hard?

You know, you’ve got these axioms.

They’re very small.

Why can’t you just solve every problem in math easily?

Yeah, it’s just logic.

Right, yeah.

Well, logic happens to be a particular special case

that does have certain simplicity to it.

But general mathematics, even arithmetic,

already doesn’t have the simplicity that logic has.

So why is it hard?

Because of computational irreducibility.

Right.

Because what happens is, to know what’s true,

and this is this whole story about the path

you have to follow and how long is the path,

and Gödel’s theorem is the statement

that the path is not a bounded length,

but the fact that the path is not always compressible

to something tiny is a story of computational irreducibility.

So that’s why math is hard.

Now, the next question is, why is math doable?

Because it might be the case that most things you care about

don’t have finite length paths.

Most things you care about might be things

where you get lost in the sea of computational irreducibility

and worse, undecidability.

That is, there’s just no finite length path

that gets you there.

Why is mathematics doable?

Gödel proved his incompleteness theorem in 1931.

Most working mathematicians don’t really care about it.

They just go ahead and do mathematics,

even though it could be that the questions they’re asking

are undecidable.

It could have been that Fermat’s last theorem

is undecidable.

It turned out it had a proof.

It’s a long, complicated proof.

The twin prime conjecture might be undecidable.

The Riemann hypothesis might be undecidable.

These things might be, the axioms of mathematics

might not be strong enough to reach those statements.

It might be the case that depending on what axioms

you choose, you can either say that’s true

or that’s not true.

So…

And by the way, from Fermat’s last theorem,

there could be a shorter path.

Absolutely.

Yeah, so the notion of geodesics in metamathematical space

is the notion of shortest proofs in metamathematical space.

And that’s a, you know, human mathematicians

do not find shortest paths,

nor do automated theorem provers.

But the fact, and by the way, the, I mean,

this stuff is so bizarrely connected.

I mean, if you’re into automated theorem proving,

there are these so called critical pair lemmas

and automated theorem proving.

Those are precisely the branch pairs in our,

that in multiway graphs.

Let me just finish on the why mathematics is doable.

Oh yes, the second part.

So you know why it’s hard, why is it doable?

Right, why do we not just get lost

in undecidability all the time?

Yeah.

So, and here’s another fact,

is in doing computer experiments

and doing experimental mathematics,

you do get lost in that way.

When you just say, I’m picking a random integer equation.

How do I, does it have a solution or not?

And you just pick it at random

without any human sort of path getting there.

Often, it’s really, really hard.

It’s really hard to answer those questions.

We just pick them at random from the space of possibilities.

But what I think is happening is,

and that’s a case where you just fell off

into this ocean of sort of irreducibility and so on.

What’s happening is human mathematics

is a story of building a path.

You started off, you’re always building out

on this path where you are proving things.

You’ve got this proof trajectory

and you’re basically, the human mathematics

is the sort of the exploration of the world

along this proof trajectory, so to speak.

You’re not just parachuting in from anywhere.

You’re following Lewis and Clark or whatever.

You’re actually going, doing the path.

And the fact that you are constrained to go along that path

is the reason you don’t end up with,

every so often you’ll see a little piece of undecidability

and you’ll avoid that part of the path.

But that’s basically the story of why human mathematics

has seemed to be doable.

It’s a story of exploring these paths

that are by their nature,

they have been constructed to be paths that can be followed.

And so you can follow them further.

Now, why is this relevant to anything?

So, okay, so here’s my belief.

The fact that human mathematics works that way

is I think there’s some sort of connections

between the way that observers work in physics

and the way that the axiom systems of mathematics are set up

to make mathematics be doable in that kind of way.

And so, in other words, in particular,

I think there is an analog of causal invariance,

which I think is, and this is again,

it’s sort of the upper reaches of mathematics

and stuff that it’s a thing,

there’s this thing called homotopy type theory,

which is an abstract, it’s came out of category theory,

and it’s sort of an abstraction of mathematics.

Mathematics itself is an abstraction,

but it’s an abstraction of the abstraction of mathematics.

And there is the thing called the univalence axiom,

which is a sort of a key axiom in that set of ideas.

And I’m pretty sure the univalence axiom

is equivalent to causal invariance.

What was the term you used again?

Univalence.

Is that something for somebody like me accessible?

Or is this?

There’s a statement of it that’s fairly accessible.

I mean, the statement of it is,

basically it says things which are equivalent

can be considered to be identical.

In which space?

Yeah, it’s in higher category.

In category.

Okay, so it’s a, but I mean,

the thing just to give a sketch of how that works.

So category theory is an attempt to idealize,

it’s an attempt to sort of have a formal theory

of mathematics that is at a sort of higher level

than mathematics.

It’s where you just think about these mathematical objects

and these categories of objects and these morphisms,

these connections between categories.

Okay, so it turns out the morphisms and categories,

at least weak categories,

are very much like the paths in our hypergraphs and things.

And it turns out, again, this is where it all gets crazy.

I mean, the fact that these things are connected

is just bizarre.

So category theory, our causal graphs

are like second order category theory.

And it turns out you can take the limits

of infinite order category theory.

So just give roughly the idea.

This is a roughly explainable idea.

So a mathematical proof will be a path

that says you can get from this thing to this other thing.

And here’s the path that you get from this thing

to this other thing.

But in general, there may be many paths,

many proofs that get you many different paths

that all successfully go from this thing

to this other thing, okay?

Now you can define a higher order proof,

which is a proof of the equivalence of those proofs.

Okay, so you’re saying there’s a…

A path between those proofs essentially.

Yes, a path between the paths, okay?

And so you do that.

That’s the sort of second order thing.

That path between the paths is essentially related

to our causal graphs.

Then you can take the limit.

Wow, okay.

The path between path, between path, between path.

The infinite limit.

That infinite limit turns out to be

our Rulial Multiway System.

Yeah, the Rulial Multiway System,

that’s a fascinating, both in the physics world

and as you’re saying now, that’s fast.

I’m not sure I’ve loaded it in completely, but…

Well, I’m not sure I have either.

And it may be one of these things where,

in another five years or something, it’s like,

it was obvious, but I didn’t see it.

No, but the thing which is sort of interesting to me

is that there’s sort of an upper reach of mathematics,

of the abstraction of mathematics.

This thing, there’s this mathematician called Grothendieck

who’s generally viewed as being sort of one

of the most abstract,

sort of creator of the most abstract mathematics

of 1970s ish timeframe.

And one of the things that he constructed was this thing

he called the Infinity Grupoid.

And he has this sort of hypothesis

about the inevitable appearance of geometry

from essentially logic in the structure of this thing.

Well, it turns out this Rulial Multiway System

is the Infinity Grupoid.

So it’s this limiting object.

And this is an instance of that limiting object.

So what to me is, I mean, again,

I’ve been always afraid of this kind of mathematics

because it seemed incomprehensibly abstract to me.

But what I’m sort of excited about with this

is that we’ve sort of concretified the way

that you can reach this kind of mathematics,

which makes it, well, both seem more relevant

and also the fact that I don’t yet know exactly

what mileage we’re gonna get from using

the sort of the apparatus that’s been built

in those areas of mathematics to analyze what we’re doing.

But the thing that’s.

So both ways.

So using mathematics to understand what you’re doing

and using what you’re doing computationally

to understand that.

Right, so for example,

the understanding of metamathematical space,

one of the reasons I really want to do that

is because I want to understand quantum mechanics better.

And that, what you see,

we live that kind of the multiway graph of mathematics

because we actually know this is a theorem we’ve heard of.

This is another one we’ve heard of.

We can actually say these are actual things in the world

that we relate to,

which we can’t really do as readily for the physics case.

And so it’s kind of a way to help my intuition.

It’s also, there are bizarre things

like what’s the analog of Einstein’s equations

in metamathematical space?

What’s the analog of a black hole?

It turns out it looks like not completely sure yet,

but there’s this notion of nonconstructive proofs

in mathematics.

And I think those relate to,

well, actually they relate to things

related to event horizons.

So the fact that you can take ideas from physics

like event horizons.

And map them into the same kind of space, metamath.

It’s really.

So do you think there’ll be,

do you think you might stumble upon

some breakthrough ideas in theorem proving?

Like for, from the other direction?

Yeah, yeah, yeah.

No, I mean, what’s really nice is that we are using,

so this absolutely directly maps to theorem proving.

So pods and multiway graphs,

that’s what a theorem prover is trying to do.

But I also mean like automated theorem.

Yeah, yeah, yeah.

That’s what, right.

So the finding of pods, the finding of shortest pods

or finding of pods at all

is what automated theorem provers do.

And actually what we’ve been doing.

So we’ve actually been using automated theorem proving

both in the physics project to prove things

and using that as a way to understand multiway graphs.

And because what an automated theorem prover is doing

is it’s trying to find a path through a multiway graph

and its critical pair lemmas

are precisely little stubs of branch pairs

going off into branchial space.

And that’s, I mean, it’s really weird.

You know, we have these visualizations in Wolfram language

of proof graphs from our automated theorem proving system.

And they look reminiscent of.

Well, it’s just bizarre

because we made these up a few years ago

and they have these little triangle things

and they are, we didn’t quite get it right.

We didn’t quite get the analogy perfectly right,

but it’s very close.

You know, just to say,

in terms of how these things are connected.

So there’s another bizarre connection

that I have to mention because which is,

which again, we don’t fully know,

but it’s a connection to something else

you might not have thought was in the slightest

but connected, which is distributed blockchain like things.

Now you might figure out that that’s,

you would figure out that that’s connected

because it’s a story of distributed computing.

And the issue, you know, with the blockchain,

you’re saying there’s going to be this one ledger

that globally says, this is what happened in the world.

But that’s a bad deal.

If you’ve got all these different transactions

that are happening and you know,

this transaction in country A

doesn’t have to be reconciled with the transaction

in country B, at least not for a while.

And that story is just like what happens

with our causal graphs.

That whole reconciliation thing is just like

what happens with light cones and all this kind of thing.

That’s where the causal awareness comes into play.

I mean, that’s, you know,

most of your conversations are about physics,

but it’s kind of funny that this probably

and possibly might have even bigger impact

and revolutionary ideas and totally other disciplines.

Right, well, you see, yeah, right.

So the question is, why is that happening, right?

And the reason it’s happening,

I’ve thought about this obviously,

because I like to think about these meta questions of,

you know, what’s happening is this model that we have

is an incredibly minimal model.

And once you have an incredibly minimal model,

and this happened with cellular automata as well,

cellular automata are an incredibly minimal model.

And so it’s inevitable that it gets you,

it’s sort of an upstream thing

that gets used in lots of different places.

And it’s like, you know, the fact that it gets used,

you know, cellular automata is sort of a minimal model

of let’s say road traffic flow or something.

And they’re also a minimal model of something in,

you know, chemistry,

and they’re also a minimal model of something

in epidemiology, right?

It’s because they’re such a simple model that they can,

that they apply to all these different things.

Similarly, this model that we have with the physics project

is another, cellular automata are a minimal model

of parallel, of basically of parallel computation

where you’ve defined space and time.

These models are minimal models

where you have not defined space and time.

And they have been very hard to understand in the past,

but the, I think the,

perhaps the most important breakthrough there

is the realization that these are models of physics.

And therefore that you can use everything

that’s been developed in physics

to get intuition about how things like that work.

And that’s why you can potentially use ideas from physics

to get intuition about how to do parallel computing.

And because the underlying model is the same.

But we have all of this achievement in physics.

I mean, you know, you might say,

oh, you’ve come up with the fundamental theory of physics

that throws out what people have done in physics before.

Well, it doesn’t, but also the real power

is to use what’s been done before in physics

to apply it in these other places.

Yes, absolutely.

This kind of brings up,

I know you probably don’t particularly love commenting

on the work of others,

but let me bring up a couple of personalities

just because it’s fun and people are curious about it.

So there’s Sabine Hassenfelder.

I don’t know if you’re familiar with her.

She wrote this book that I need to read,

but I forget what the title is,

but it’s Beauty Leads Us Astray in Physics

is a subtitle or something like that.

Which so much about what we’re talking about now,

like this simplification,

to us humans seems to be beautiful.

Like there’s a certain intuition with physicists,

with people that a simple theory,

like this reducibility,

pockets of reducibility is the ultimate goal.

And I think what she tries to argue is no,

we just need to come up with theories

that are just really good at predicting physical phenomena.

It’s okay to have a bunch of disparate theories

as opposed to trying to chase this beautiful theory

of everything is the ultimate beautiful theory,

a simple one.

What’s your response to that?

Well, so what you’re quoting,

I don’t know the Sabine Hassenfelder’s,

exactly what she said,

but I mean that you’re quoting the title of her book.

Okay.

Let me respond to what you were describing,

which may or may not have nothing to do with

what Sabine Hassenfelder says or thinks.

Sorry, Sabine.

Right.

Sorry for misquoting.

But I mean, the question is,

is beauty a guide to whether something is correct?

Which is kind of also the story of Occam’s razor.

If you’ve got a bunch of different explanations of things,

is the thing that is the simplest explanation

likely to be the correct explanation?

And there are situations where that’s true

and there are situations where it isn’t true.

Sometimes in human systems, it is true

because people have kind of,

in evolutionary systems, sometimes it’s true

because it’s sort of been kicked

to the point where it’s minimized.

But in physics, does Occam’s razor work?

Is there a simple, quotes, beautiful explanation for things

or is it a big mess?

We don’t intrinsically know.

I think that the, I wouldn’t,

before I worked on the project in recent times,

I would have said,

we do not know how complicated

the rule for the universe will be.

And I would have said, the one thing we know,

which is a fundamental fact about science,

that’s the thing that makes science possible,

is that there is order in the universe.

I mean, early theologians would have used that

as an argument for the existence of God

because it’s like, why is there order in the universe?

Why doesn’t every single particle in the universe

just do its own thing?

Something must be making there be order in the universe.

We, in the sort of early theology point of view,

that’s the role of God is to do that, so to speak.

In our, we might say,

it’s the role of a formal theory to do that.

And then the question is,

but how simple should that theory be?

And should that theory be one that,

where I think the point is, if it’s simple,

it’s almost inevitably somewhat beautiful

in the sense that, because all the stuff that we see

has to fit into this little tiny theory.

And the way it does that has to be,

it depends on your notion of beauty,

but I mean, for me, the sort of the surprising

connectivity of it is, at least in my aesthetic,

that’s something that responds to my aesthetic.

But the question is, I mean,

you’re a fascinating person in the sense that

you’re at once talking about computational,

the fundamental computational reducibility of the universe,

and on the other hand,

trying to come up with a theory of everything,

which simply describes the,

the simple origins of that computational reducibility.

I mean, both of those things are kind of,

it’s paralyzing to think that we can’t make any sense

of the universe in the general case,

but it’s hopeful to think like,

one, we can think of a rule

and that generates this whole complexity,

and two, we can find pockets of reducibility

that are powerful for everyday life

to do different kinds of predictions.

I suppose Sabine wants to find,

focus on the finding of small pockets of reducibility

versus the theory of everything.

You know, it’s a funny thing because,

you know, a bunch of people have started working

on this physics project,

people who are physicists, basically,

and it is really a fascinating sociological phenomenon

because what, you know,

when I was working on this before in the 1990s,

you know, wrote it up, put it,

it’s 100 pages of this 1200 page book

that I wrote, New Kind of Science,

is, you know, 100 pages of that is about physics,

but I saw it at that time,

not as a pinnacle achievement,

but rather as a use case, so to speak.

I mean, my main point was this new kind of science,

and it’s like, you can apply it to biology,

you can apply it to, you know, other kinds of physics,

you can apply it to fundamental physics,

it’s just an application, so to speak,

it’s not the core thing.

But then, you know, one of the things that was interesting

with that book was, you know,

book comes out, lots of people think it’s pretty interesting

and lots of people start using what it has

in different kinds of fields.

The one field where there was sort of a heavy pitchforking

was from my friends, the fundamental physics people,

which was, it’s like, no,

this can’t possibly be right.

And, you know, it’s like, you know,

if what you’re doing is right,

it’ll overturn 50 years of what we’ve been doing.

And it’s like, no, it won’t, was what I was saying.

And it’s like, but, you know, for a while,

when I started, you know, I was going to go on back in 2002,

well, 2004, actually, I was going to go on

working on this project.

And I actually stopped,

partly because it’s like, why am I, you know,

this is like, I’ve been in business a long time, right?

I’m building a product for a target market

that doesn’t want the product.

And it’s like.

Why work, yeah, yeah, why work against the,

swim against the current or whatever.

Right, but you see what’s happened,

which is sort of interesting is that,

so a couple of things happened and it was like,

you know, it was like, I don’t want to do this project

because I can do so many other things,

which I’m really interested in where, you know,

people say, great, thanks for those tools.

Thanks for those ideas, et cetera.

Whereas, you know, if you’re dealing with kind of a,

you know, a sort of a structure where people are saying,

no, no, we don’t want this new stuff.

We don’t need any new stuff.

We’re really fine with what we’re doing.

Yeah, there’s like literally like, I don’t know,

millions of people who are thankful for Wolfram Alpha.

A bunch of people wrote to me, how thankful,

they are a different crowd

than the theoretical physics community, perhaps.

Yeah, well, but you know,

the theoretical physics community

pretty much uniformly uses Wolfram language

and Mathematica, right?

And so it’s kind of like, you know, and that’s,

but the thing is what happens, you know,

this is what happens, mature fields do not, you know,

it’s like, we’re doing what we’re doing.

We have the methods that we have

and we’re just fine here.

Now what’s happened in the last 18 years or so,

I think there’s a couple of things have happened.

First of all, the hope that, you know,

string theory or whatever would deliver

the fundamental theory of physics,

that hope has disappeared.

That the, another thing that’s happened

is the sort of the interest in computation around physics

has been greatly enhanced

by the whole quantum information,

quantum computing story.

People, you know, the idea there might be something

sort of computational related to physics

has somehow grown.

And I think, you know, it’s sort of interesting.

I mean, right now, if we say, you know,

it’s like, if you’re like,

who else is trying to come up

with the fundamental theory of physics?

It’s like, there aren’t professional,

no professional physicists, no professional physicists.

What are your, I mean, you’ve talked with him,

but just as a matter of personalities,

cause it’s a beautiful story.

What are your thoughts about Eric Weinstein’s work?

You know, I think his, I mean,

he did a PhD thesis in mathematical physics at Harvard.

He’s a mathematical physicist.

And, you know, it seems like it’s kind of,

you know, it’s in that framework.

And it’s kind of like,

I’m not sure how much further it’s got than his PhD thesis,

which was 20 years ago or something.

And I think that, you know, the, you know,

it’s a fairly specific piece of mathematical physics.

That’s quite nice.

And…

What trajectory do you hope it takes?

I mean…

Well, I think in his particular case,

I mean, from what I understand,

which is not everything at all,

but, you know, I think I know the rough tradition,

at least what he’s operating in is sort of theory of gauge theories.

Gauge theories, yeah.

Local gauge invariants and so on.

Okay, we are very close to understanding

how local gauge invariants works in our models.

And it’s very beautiful.

And it’s very…

And, you know, does some of the mathematical structure

that he’s enthusiastic about fit?

Quite possibly, yes.

So there might be a possibility of trying to understand

how those things fit, how gauge theory fits.

Yeah, very well.

I mean, the question is, you know,

so there are a couple of things

one might try to get in the world.

So for example, it’s like,

can we get three dimensions of space?

We haven’t managed to get that yet.

Gauge theory, the standard model of particle physics says,

but it’s SU3 cross SU2 cross U1.

Those are the designations of these Lie groups.

It doesn’t, but anyway,

so those are sort of representations

of symmetries of the theory.

And so, you know, it is conceivable

that it is generically true.

Okay, so all those are subgroups of a group called E8,

which is a weird, exceptional Lie group, okay?

It is conceivable, I don’t know whether it’s the case,

that that will be generic in these models,

that it will be generic,

that the gauge invariance of the model has this property,

just as things like general relativity,

which corresponds to the thing called general covariance,

which is another gauge like invariance.

It could conceivably be the case

that the kind of local gauge invariance

that we see in particle physics is somehow generic.

And that would be a, you know,

the thing that’s really cool, I think, you know,

sociologically, although this hasn’t really hit yet,

is that all of these different things,

all these different things people have been working on

in these, in some cases,

quite abstruse areas of mathematical physics,

an awful lot of them seem to tie into what we’re doing.

And, you know, it might not be that way.

Yeah, absolutely.

That’s a beautiful thing, I think.

I mean, but the reason Eric Weinstein is important

is to the point that you mentioned before,

which is, it’s strange that the theory of everything

is not at the core of the passion, the dream,

the focus, the funding of the physics community.

It’s too hard.

It’s too hard and people gave up.

I mean, basically what happened is ancient Greece,

people thought we’re nearly there.

You know, the world is made of platonic solids.

It’s, you know, water is a tetrahedron or something.

We’re almost there, okay?

Long period of time where people were like,

no, we don’t know how it works.

You know, time of Newton, you know, we’re almost there.

Everything is gravitation.

You know, time of Faraday and Maxwell, we’re almost there.

Everything is fields, everything is the ether, you know?

Then…

And the whole time we’re making big progress though.

Oh yes, absolutely.

But the fundamental theory of physics is almost a footnote

because it’s like, it’s the machine code.

It’s like we’re operating in the high level languages.

Yeah.

You know, that’s what we really care about.

That’s what’s relevant for our everyday physics.

You talked about different centuries

and the 21st century will be everything is computation.

Yes.

If that takes us all the way, we don’t know,

but it might take us pretty far.

Yes, right, that’s right.

And I, but I think the point is that it’s like, you know,

if you’re doing biology, you might say,

how can you not be really interested in the origin of life

and the definition of life?

Well, it’s irrelevant.

You know, you’re studying the properties of some virus.

It doesn’t matter, you know, where, you know,

you’re operating at some much higher level.

And it’s the same, what’s happening with physics is,

I was sort of surprised actually.

I was sort of mapping out this history of people’s efforts

to understand the fundamental theory of physics.

And it’s remarkable how little has been done on this question.

And it’s, you know, because, you know,

there’ve been times when there’s been bursts of enthusiasm.

Oh, we’re almost there.

And then it decays and people just say,

oh, it’s too hard, but it’s not relevant anyway.

And I think that the thing that, you know,

so the question of, you know, one question is,

why does anybody, why should anybody care, right?

Why should anybody care

what the fundamental theory of physics is?

I think it’s intellectually interesting,

but what will be the sort of,

what will be the impact of this?

What, I mean, this is the key question.

What do you think will happen

if we figure out the fundamental theory of physics?

Right.

Outside of the intellectual curiosity of us.

Okay, so here’s my best guess, okay?

So if you look at the history of science,

I think a very interesting analogy is Copernicus.

Okay, so what did Copernicus do?

There’d been this Ptolemaic system

for working out the motion of planets.

It did pretty well.

It used epicycles, et cetera, et cetera, et cetera.

It had all this computational ways

of working out where planets will be.

When we work out where planets are today,

we’re basically using epicycles.

But Copernicus had this different way of formulating things

in which he said, you know,

and the earth is going around the sun,

and that had a consequence.

The consequence was you can use this mathematical theory

to conclude something which is absolutely not

what we can tell from common sense, right?

So it’s like, trust the mathematics, trust the science, okay?

Now fast forward 400 years,

and now we’re in this pandemic,

and it’s kind of like everybody thinks the science

will figure out everything.

It’s like from the science,

we can just figure out what to do.

We can figure out everything.

That was before Copernicus.

Nobody would have thought if the science says something

that doesn’t agree with our everyday experience,

where we just have to compute the science

and then figure out what to do,

people would say that’s completely crazy.

And so your sense is,

once we figure out the framework of computation

that can basically do any,

understand the fabric of reality,

we’ll be able to derive totally counterintuitive things.

No, the point I think is the following.

That right now, you know,

I talk about computational irreducibility.

People, you know, I was very proud

that I managed to get the term computational irreducibility

into the congressional record last year.

That’s right, by the way,

that’s a whole nother topic we could talk about.

Fascinating. Different topic.

Different topic.

But Tim, in any case, you know,

but so computational irreducibility

is one of these sort of concepts

that I think is important in understanding

lots of things in the world.

But the question is, it’s only important

if you believe the world is fundamentally computational.

Right?

But if you know the fundamental theory of physics

and it’s fundamentally computational,

then you’ve rooted the whole thing.

That is, you know the world is computational.

And while you can discuss whether, you know,

it’s not the case that people would say,

well, you have this whole computational irreducibility,

all these features of computation.

We don’t care about those

because after all the world isn’t computational,

you might say.

But if you know, you know, base, base, base thing,

physics is computational,

then you know that that stuff is, you know,

that that’s kind of the grounding for that stuff.

Just as in a sense Copernicus was the grounding

for the idea that you could figure out something

with math and science

that was not what you would intuitively think

from your senses.

So now we’ve got to this point where, for example,

we say, you know, once we have the idea

that computation is the foundational thing

that explains our whole universe,

then we have to say, well, what does it mean

for other things?

Like it means there’s computational irreducibility.

That means science is limited in certain ways.

That means this, that means that.

But the fact that we have that grounding means that,

you know, and I think, for example, for Copernicus,

for instance, the implications of his work

on the set of mathematics of astronomy were cool,

but they involved a very small number of people.

The implications of his work for sort of the philosophy

of how you think about things were vast

and involved, you know, everybody more or less.

But do you think, so that’s actually the way scientists

and people see the world around us.

So it has a huge impact in that sense.

Do you think it might have an impact more directly

to engineering derivations from physics,

like propulsion systems, our ability to colonize the world?

Like, for example, okay, this is like sci fi,

but if you understand the computational nature, say,

of the different forces of physics, you know,

there’s a notion of being able to warp gravity,

things like this.

Yeah, can we make warp drive?

Warp drive, yeah.

So like, would we be able to, will, you know,

will like Elon Musk start paying attention?

Like it’s awfully costly to launch these rockets.

Do you think we’ll be able to, yeah, create warp drive?

And, you know, I set myself some homework.

I agreed to give a talk at some NASA workshop

in a few weeks about faster than light travel.

So I haven’t figured it out yet, but no, but.

You got two weeks.

Yeah, right.

But do you think that kind of understanding

of fundamental theory of physics can lead

to those engineering breakthroughs?

Okay, I think it’s far away, but I’m not certain.

I mean, you know, this is the thing that,

I set myself an exercise when gravity waves,

gravitational waves were discovered, right?

I set myself the exercise of what would black hole

technology look like?

In other words, right now, you know,

black holes are far away.

They’re, you know, how on earth can we do things with them?

But just imagine that we could get, you know,

pet black holes right in our backyard.

You know, what kind of technology could we build with them?

I got a certain distance, not that far,

but I think in, you know, so there are ideas, you know,

I have this, one of the weirder ideas is things

I’m calling space tunnels,

which are higher dimensional pieces of space time,

where basically you can, you know,

in our three dimensional space,

there might be a five dimensional, you know,

region, which actually will appear as a white hole

at one end and a black hole at the other end,

you know, who knows whether they exist.

And then the questions, another one,

okay, this is another crazy one,

is the thing that I’m calling a vacuum cleaner, okay?

So, I mentioned that, you know,

there’s all this activity in the universe,

which is maintaining the structure of space.

And that leads to a certain energy density

effectively in space.

And so the question, in fact, dark energy

is a story of essentially negative mass

produced by the absence of energy

you thought would be there, so to speak.

And we don’t know exactly how it works

in either our model or the physical universe,

but this notion of a vacuum cleaner is a thing where,

you know, you have all these things

that are maintaining the structure of space,

but what if you could clean out some of that stuff

that’s maintaining the structure of space

and make a simpler vacuum somewhere?

You know, what would that do?

A totally different kind of vacuum.

Right, and that would lead to negative energy density,

which would need to, so gravity is usually

a purely attractive force, but negative mass

would lead to repulsive gravity

and lead to all kinds of weird things.

Now, can it be done in our universe?

You know, my immediate thought is no,

but you know, the fact is that, okay, so here’s the thing.

Well, once you understand the fact,

because you’re saying like, at this level of abstraction,

can we reach to the lower levels and mess with it?

Yes.

Once you understand the levels, I think you can start to.

I know, and I’m, you know, I have to say

that this reminds me of people telling one years ago

that, you know, you’ll never transmit data

over a copper wire at more than 1,000,

you know, 1,000 board or something, right?

And this is, why did that not happen?

You know, why do we have this much,

much faster data transmission?

Because we’ve understood many more of the details

of what’s actually going on.

And it’s the same exact story here.

And it’s the same, you know, I think that this,

as I say, I think one of the features of sort of,

one of the things about our time

that will seem incredibly naive in the future

is the belief that, you know, things like heat

is just random motion of molecules,

that it’s just throw up your hands, it’s just random.

We can’t say anything about it.

That will seem naive.

Yeah, at the heat death of the universe,

those particles would be laughing at us humans thinking.

Yes, right.

That life is not beautiful.

I’ll have a whole civilization, you know.

Humans used to think they’re special

with their little brains.

Well, right, but also, and they used to think

that this would just be random and uninteresting.

But that’s, but so this question about whether you can,

you know, mess with the underlying structure

and how you find a way to mess with the underlying structure,

that’s a, you know, I have to say, you know,

my immediate thing is, boy, that seems really hard,

but then, and you know,

possibly computational irreducibility will bite you,

but then there’s always some path

of computational reducibility.

And that path of computational reducibility

is the engineering invention that has to be made.

Those little pockets can have huge engineering impact.

Right, and I think that that’s right.

And I mean, we live in, you know, we make use of so many

of those pockets.

And the fact is, you know, I, you know, this is, yes,

it’s a, you know, it’s one of these things where,

where, you know, I’m a person who likes to figure out ideas

and so on, and the sort of tests of my level of imagination,

so to speak.

And so a couple of places where there’s sort of serious

humility in terms of my level of imagination,

one is this thing about different reference frames

for understanding the universe,

where like, imagine the physics of the aliens,

what will it be like?

And I’m like, that’s really hard.

I don’t know, you know?

And I mean, I think that…

But once you have the framework in place,

you can at least reason about the things you don’t know,

maybe can’t know, or like, it’s too hard for you to know,

but then the mathematics can, that’s exactly it,

allow you to reach beyond where you can reason about.

So I’m, you know, I’m trying to not have, you know,

if you think back to Alan Turing, for example,

and, you know, when he invented Turing machines, you know,

and imagining what computers would end up doing,

so to speak.

Yeah.

You know, and it’s…

It’s very difficult.

It’s difficult, right.

And it’s, and I mean, this thing…

Made a few reasonable predictions,

but most of it, he couldn’t predict, possibly.

By the time, by 1950, he was making reasonable predictions

about some things.

But not the 30s, yeah.

Right, not when he first, you know, conceptualized,

you know, and he conceptualized universal computing

for a very specific mathematical reason

that wasn’t as general.

But yes, it’s a good sort of exercise in humility

to realize that it’s kind of like,

it’s really hard to figure these things out.

The engineering of the universe,

if we know how the universe works, how can we engineer it?

That’s such a beautiful vision.

By the way, I have to mention one more thing,

which is the ultimate question from physics is,

okay, so we have this abstract model of the universe.

Why does the universe exist at all, right?

So, you know, we might say there is a formal model

that if you run this model, you get the universe,

or the model gives you, you know, a model of the universe,

right, you run this mathematical thing

and the mathematics unfolds in the way

that corresponds to the universe.

But the question is, why was that actualized?

Why does the actual universe actually exist?

And so this is another one of these humility

and it’s like, can you figure this out?

I have a guess, okay, about the answer to that.

And my guess is somewhat unsatisfying,

but my guess is that it’s a little bit similar

to Gödel’s second incompleteness theorem,

which is the statement that from within,

as an axiomatic theory like piano arithmetic,

you cannot from within that theory

prove the consistency of the theory.

So my guess is that for entities within the universe,

there is no finite determination that can be made

of the statement the universe exists

is essentially undecidable to any entity

that is embedded in the universe.

Within that universe, how does that make you feel?

Does that put you at peace that it’s impossible,

or is it really ultimately frustrating?

Well, I think it just says that it’s not a kind of question

that, you know, there are things that it is reasonable.

I mean, there’s kinds of, you know,

you can talk about hyper computation as well.

You can say, imagine there was a hyper computer,

here’s what it would do.

So okay, great, it would be lovely to have a hyper computer,

but unfortunately we can’t make it in the universe.

Like it would be lovely to answer this,

but unfortunately we can’t do it in the universe.

And you know, this is all we have, so to speak.

And I think it’s really just a statement.

It’s sort of, in the end, it’ll be a kind of a logical,

logically inevitable statement, I think.

I think it will be something where it is,

as you understand what it means to have,

what it means to have a sort of predicate of existence

and what it means to have these kinds of things,

it will sort of be inevitable that this has to be the case,

that from within that universe, you can’t establish

the reason for its existence, so to speak.

You can’t prove that it exists and so on.

And nevertheless, because of computational reducibility,

the future is ultimately not predictable, full of mystery,

and that’s what makes life worth living.

Right, I mean, right.

And you know, it’s funny for me,

because as a pure sort of human being doing what I do,

it’s, you know, like I’m interested in people,

I like sort of the whole human experience, so to speak.

And yet, it’s a little bit weird when I’m thinking,

you know, it’s all hypergraphs down there,

and it’s all just.

Hypergraphs all the way down.

Right.

It’s like turtles all the way down.

Yeah, yeah, right.

And it’s kind of, you know, to me, it is a funny thing,

because every so often I get this, you know,

as I’m thinking about, I think we’ve really gotten,

you know, we’ve really figured out kind of the essence

of how physics works, and I’m like thinking to myself,

you know, here’s this physical thing,

and I’m like, you know,

this feels like a very definite thing.

How can it be the case that this is just

some rule or reference frame of, you know,

this infinite creature that is so abstract and so on?

And I kind of, it is a, it’s a funny sort of feeling

that, you know, we are, we’re sort of, it’s like,

in the end, it’s just sort of,

we’re just happy we’re just humans type thing.

And it’s kind of like, but we’re making,

we make things as, it’s not like we’re just a tiny speck.

We are, in a sense, the, we are more important

by virtue of the fact that, in a sense,

it’s not like there’s, there is no ultimate, you know,

it’s like, we’re important because,

because, you know, we’re here, so to speak,

and we’re not, it’s not like there’s a thing

where we’re saying, you know, we are just but one

sort of intelligence out of all these other intelligences.

And so, you know, ultimately there’ll be

the super intelligence, which is all of these put together

and they’ll be very different from us.

No, it’s actually going to be equivalent to us.

And the thing that makes us a sort of special

is just the details of us, so to speak.

It’s not something where we can say,

oh, there’s this other thing, you know,

just, you think humans are cool,

just wait until you’ve seen this.

You know, it’s going to be much more impressive.

Well, no, it’s all going to be

kind of computationally equivalent.

And the thing that, you know, it’s not going to be,

oh, this thing is amazingly much more impressive

and amazingly much more meaningful, let’s say.

No, we’re it.

I mean, that’s the…

And the symbolism of this particular moment.

So this has been one of the,

one of the favorite conversations I’ve ever had, Stephen.

It’s a huge honor to talk to you,

to talk about a topic like this for four plus hours

on the fundamental theory of physics.

And yet we’re just two finite descendants of apes

that have to end this conversation

because darkness have come upon us.

Right, and we’re going to get bitten by mosquitoes

and all kinds of terrible things.

The symbolism of that,

we’re talking about the most basic fabric of reality

and having to end because of the fact that things end.

It’s tragic and beautiful, Stephen.

Thank you so much.

Huge honor.

I can’t wait to see what you do in the next couple of days

and next week, a month.

We’re all watching with excitement.

Thank you so much.

Thanks.

Thanks for listening to this conversation

with Stephen Wolfram.

And thank you to our sponsors,

SimplySafe, Sun Basket, and Masterclass.

Please check out our sponsors in the description

to get a discount and to support this podcast.

If you enjoy this thing, subscribe on YouTube,

review it with five stars on Apple Podcasts,

follow on Spotify, support on Patreon,

or connect with me on Twitter at Lex Friedman.

And now let me leave you with some words

from Richard Feynman.

Physics isn’t the most important thing, love is.

Thank you for listening and hope to see you next time.

comments powered by Disqus